Max Weber |
German sociologist, philosopher, and political economist |
Born |
Maximilian Karl Emil Weber
(1864-04-21)21 April 1864
Erfurt, Saxony, Kingdom of Prussia |
Died |
14 June 1920(1920-06-14) (aged 56) (pneumonia)
Munich, Bavaria, Germany |
Nationality |
German |
Fields |
Economics, sociology, history, law, politics, philosophy |
Institutions |
University of Berlin, University of Freiburg, University of Heidelberg, University of Vienna, University of Munich |
Alma mater |
University of Berlin, University of Heidelberg |
Doctoral advisor |
Levin Goldschmidt |
Known for |
Bureaucracy, Disenchantment, Ideal type, Iron cage, Life chances, Methodological individualism, Monopoly on violence, Protestant work ethic, Rationalisation, Social action, Three-component theory of stratification, Tripartite classification of authority, Verstehen |
Influences |
Immanuel Kant, Friedrich Nietzsche, Wilhelm Dilthey, Heinrich Rickert, Georg Simmel, Werner Sombart |
Influenced |
Karl Jaspers, Talcott Parsons, Ludwig von Mises, György Lukács, Theodor W. Adorno, Jürgen Habermas, Joseph Schumpeter |
Maximilian Karl Emil "Max" Weber (German pronunciation: [ˈmaks ˈveːbɐ]; 21 April 1864 – 14 June 1920) was a German sociologist, philosopher, and political economist who profoundly influenced social theory, social research, and the discipline of sociology itself.[1]
Weber was a key proponent of methodological antipositivism, presenting sociology as a non-empiricist field which must study social action through interpretive means based upon understanding the meanings and purposes that individuals attach to their own actions. Weber is often cited, with Émile Durkheim and Karl Marx, as one of the three principal architects of modern social science.[2][3][4]
Weber's main intellectual concern was understanding the processes of rationalisation, secularization, and "disenchantment" that he associated with the rise of capitalism and modernity.[5] Weber argued that the most important difference among societies is not how people produce things but how people think about the world. In Weber’s view, modern society was the product of a new way of thinking.[6] Weber is perhaps best known for his thesis combining economic sociology and the sociology of religion, elaborated in his book The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Weber proposed that ascetic Protestantism was one of the major "elective affinities" associated with the rise of capitalism, bureaucracy and the rational-legal nation-state in the Western world. Against Marx's "historical materialism," Weber emphasised the importance of cultural influences embedded in religion as a means for understanding the genesis of capitalism.[7] The Protestant Ethic formed the earliest part in Weber's broader investigations into world religion: he would go on to examine the religions of China, the religions of India and ancient Judaism, with particular regard to the apparent non-development of capitalism in the corresponding societies, as well as to their differing forms of social stratification.[a]
In another major work, Politics as a Vocation, Weber defined the state as an entity which successfully claims a "monopoly on the legitimate use of violence". He was also the first to categorize social authority into distinct forms, which he labelled as charismatic, traditional, and rational-legal. His analysis of bureaucracy emphasised that modern state institutions are increasingly based on rational-legal authority. Weber also made a variety of other contributions in economic history, as well as economic theory and methodology. Weber's thought on modernity and rationalisation would come to facilitate critical theory of the Frankfurt school.
After the First World War, Max Weber was among the founders of the liberal German Democratic Party. He also ran unsuccessfully for a seat in parliament and served as advisor to the committee that drafted the ill-fated democratic Weimar Constitution of 1919. After contracting the Spanish flu, he died of pneumonia in 1920, aged 56.[2]
Weber was born in 1864, in Erfurt, Thuringia.[2] He was the eldest of the seven children of Max Weber Sr., a wealthy and prominent civil servant and member of the National Liberal Party, and his wife Helene (Fallenstein), who partly descended from French Huguenot immigrants and held strong moral absolutist ideas.[2][8] Weber Sr.'s involvement in public life immersed his home in both politics and academia, as his salon welcomed many prominent scholars and public figures.[2] The young Weber and his brother Alfred, who also became a sociologist and economist, thrived in this intellectual atmosphere. Weber's 1876 Christmas presents to his parents, when he was thirteen years old, were two historical essays entitled "About the course of German history, with special reference to the positions of the Emperor and the Pope," and "About the Roman Imperial period from Constantine to the migration of nations."[9] In class, bored and unimpressed with the teachers – who in turn resented what they perceived as a disrespectful attitude – he secretly read all forty volumes of Goethe.[10][11] Before entering the university, he would read many other classical works.[11] Over time, Weber would also be significantly affected by the marital tension between his father, "a man who enjoyed earthly pleasures," and his mother, a devout Calvinist "who sought to lead an ascetic life."[12][13]
Max Weber and his brothers,
Alfred and Karl, in 1879
In 1882 Weber enrolled in the University of Heidelberg as a law student.[14] After a year of military service he transferred to University of Berlin.[10] After his first few years as a student, during which he spent much time "drinking beer and fencing," Weber would increasingly take his mother's side in family arguments and grew estranged from his father.[12][13][15] Simultaneously with his studies, he worked as a junior barrister.[10] In 1886 Weber passed the examination for Referendar, comparable to the bar association examination in the British and American legal systems. Throughout the late 1880s, Weber continued his study of law and history.[10] He earned his law doctorate in 1889 by writing a dissertation on legal history entitled The History of Medieval Business Organisations; his advisor was Levin Goldschmidt, a respected authority in commercial law.[14][16] Two years later, Weber completed his Habilitationsschrift, The Roman Agrarian History and its Significance for Public and Private Law, working with August Meitzen.[16][17] Having thus become a Privatdozent, Weber joined the University of Berlin's faculty, lecturing and consulting for the government.[18]
In the years between the completion of his dissertation and habilitation, Weber took an interest in contemporary social policy. In 1888 he joined the Verein für Socialpolitik,[19] a new professional association of German economists affiliated with the historical school, who saw the role of economics primarily as finding solutions to the social problems of the age and who pioneered large scale statistical studies of economic issues. He also involved himself in politics, joining the left-leaning Evangelical Social Congress.[20] In 1890 the Verein established a research program to examine "the Polish question" or Ostflucht: the influx of Polish farm workers into eastern Germany as local labourers migrated to Germany's rapidly industrialising cities.[2] Weber was put in charge of the study and wrote a large part of the final report,[2][19] which generated considerable attention and controversy and marked the beginning of Weber's renown as a social scientist.[2] From 1893 to 1899 Weber was a member of the Alldeutscher Verband (Pan-German League), an organisation that campaigned against the influx of the Polish workers; the degree of Weber's support for the Germanisation of Poles and similar nationalist policies is still debated by modern scholars.[21][22]
Max Weber and his wife Marianne in 1894
Also in 1893 he married his distant cousin Marianne Schnitger, later a feminist activist and author in her own right,[2][23] who was instrumental in collecting and publishing Weber's journal articles as books after his death and her biography of him is an important source for understanding Weber's life.[24][25] They would have no children.[15] The marriage granted long-awaited financial independence to Weber, allowing him to finally leave his parents' household.[13] The couple moved to Freiburg in 1894, where Weber was appointed professor of economics at the university,[17][18] before accepting the same position at the University of Heidelberg in 1896.[17][18] There Weber became a central figure in the so-called "Weber Circle," composed of other intellectuals such as his wife Marianne, Georg Jellinek, Ernst Troeltsch, Werner Sombart, Marc Bloch, Robert Michels and György Lukács.[2] Weber also remained active in the Verein and the Evangelical Social Congress.[2] His research in that period was focused on economics and legal history.[26]
In 1897 Max Weber Sr. died, two months after a severe quarrel with his son that was never resolved.[2][27] After this, Weber became increasingly prone to depression, nervousness and insomnia, making it difficult for him to fulfill his duties as a professor.[10][17] His condition forced him to reduce his teaching and leave unfinished his course in the fall of 1899. After spending months in a sanatorium during the summer and fall of 1900, Weber and his wife travelled to Italy at the end of the year and did not return to Heidelberg until April 1902. He would again withdraw from teaching in 1903 and not return to it till 1919.[2]
After Weber's immense productivity in the early 1890s, he did not publish any papers between early 1898 and late 1902, finally resigning his professorship in late 1903. Freed from those obligations, in that year he accepted a position as associate editor of the Archives for Social Science and Social Welfare,[28] where he worked with his colleagues Edgar Jaffé and Werner Sombart.[2][29] His new interests would lie in more fundamental issues of social sciences; his works from this latter period are of primary interest to modern scholars.[26] In 1904, Weber began to publish some of his most seminal papers in this journal, notably his essay The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, which became his most famous work[30] and laid the foundations for his later research on the impact of cultures and religions on the development of economic systems.[31] This essay was the only one of his works from that period that was published as a book during his lifetime. Some other of his works written in the first one and a half decades of the 20th century – published posthumously and dedicated primarily from the fields of sociology of religion, economic and legal sociology – are also recognised as among his most important intellectual contributions.[2]
Also in 1904, he visited the United States and participated in the Congress of Arts and Sciences held in connection with the World's Fair (Louisiana Purchase Exposition) in St. Louis. Despite his partial recovery, Weber felt that he was unable to resume regular teaching at that time and continued on as a private scholar, helped by an inheritance in 1907.[18][28] In 1909, disappointed with the Verein, he co-founded the German Sociological Association (Deutsche Gesellschaft für Soziologie, or DGS) and served as its first treasurer.[2] He would, however, resign from the DGS in 1912.[2] In 1912, Weber tried to organise a left-wing political party to combine social-democrats and liberals. This attempt was unsuccessful, in part because many liberals feared social-democratic revolutionary ideals.[32]
At the outbreak of World War I, Weber, aged 50, volunteered for service and was appointed as a reserve officer and put in charge of organising the army hospitals in Heidelberg, a role he fulfilled until the end of 1915.[28][33] Weber's views on the war and the expansion of the German empire changed during the course of the conflict.[32][33][34] Early on he supported the nationalist rhetoric and the war effort, believing that the fight against the backward and despotic Russian Empire was justified and that a "liberal imperialism" along the lines of the British model would help Germany to develop a more mature political class. In time, however, Weber became one of the most prominent critics of German expansionism and of the Kaiser's war policies.[2] He publicly attacked the Belgian annexation policy and unrestricted submarine warfare and later supported calls for constitutional reform, democratisation and universal suffrage.[2]
Weber joined the worker and soldier council of Heidelberg in 1918. He then served in the German delegation to the Paris Peace Conference and as advisor to the Confidential Committee for Constitutional Reform, which drafted the Weimar Constitution.[28] Motivated by his understanding of the American model, he advocated a strong, popularly elected presidency as a constitutional counter-balance to the power of the professional bureaucracy.[2] More controversially, he also defended the provisions for emergency presidential powers that became Article 48 of the Weimar Constitution. These provisions were later used by Adolf Hitler to subvert the rest of the constitution and institute rule by decree, allowing his regime to suppress opposition and gain dictatorial powers.[35]
Weber also ran, unsuccessfully, for a parliamentary seat, as a member of the liberal German Democratic Party, which he had co-founded.[2][36] He opposed both the leftist German Revolution of 1918–1919 and the ratification of the Treaty of Versailles, a principled position that defied the political alignments in Germany at that time[2] and which may have prevented Friedrich Ebert, the new social-democratic President of Germany, from appointing Weber as minister or ambassador.[33] Weber commanded widespread respect but relatively little influence.[2] Weber's role in German politics remains controversial to this day.
Weber's grave in Heidelberg
Frustrated with politics, Weber resumed teaching during this time, first at the University of Vienna, then, after 1919, at the University of Munich.[2][18][28] His lectures from that period were collected into major works, such as the General Economic History, Science as a Vocation and Politics as a Vocation.[2] In Munich, he headed the first German university institute of sociology, but never held a professorial position in sociology. Many colleagues and students in Munich attacked his response to the German Revolution and some right-wing students held protests in front of his home.[32] Max Weber contracted the Spanish flu and died of pneumonia in Munich on 14 June 1920.[2] At the time of his death, Weber had not finished writing his magnum opus on sociological theory: Economy and Society. His widow Marianne helped prepare it for its publication in 1921–22.
Weber's thinking was strongly influenced by German idealism and particularly by neo-Kantianism, to which he had been exposed through Heinrich Rickert, his professorial colleague at the University of Freiburg.[2] Especially important to Weber's work is the neo-Kantian belief that reality is essentially chaotic and incomprehensible, with all rational order deriving from the way in which the human mind focuses its attention on certain aspects of reality and organises the resulting perceptions.[2] Weber's opinions regarding the methodology of the social sciences show parallels with the work of contemporary neo-Kantian philosopher and pioneering sociologist Georg Simmel.[37]
Weber was also influenced by Kantian ethics, which he nonetheless came to think of as obsolete in a modern age lacking in religious certainties. In this last respect, the influence of Friedrich Nietzsche's philosophy is evident.[2] According to the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, the "deep tension between the Kantian moral imperatives and a Nietzschean diagnosis of the modern cultural world is apparently what gives such a darkly tragic and agnostic shade to Weber's ethical worldview."[2] Though the influence of his mother's Calvinist religiosity is evident throughout Weber's life and work, and though he maintained a deep, life-long interest in the study of religions, Weber was open about the fact that he was personally irreligious.[38][39]
As a political economist and economic historian, Weber belonged to the "youngest" German historical school of economics, represented by academics such as Gustav von Schmoller and his student Werner Sombart. But, even though Weber's research interests were very much in line with that school, his views on methodology and the theory of value diverged significantly from those of other German historicists and were closer, in fact, to those of Carl Menger and the Austrian School, the traditional rivals of the historical school.[40][41] (See section on Economics.)
Unlike some other classical figures (Comte, Durkheim) Weber did not attempt, consciously, to create any specific set of rules governing social sciences in general, or sociology in particular.[2] Compared to Durkheim and Marx, Weber was more focused on individuals and culture and this is clear in his methodology.[10] Whereas Durkheim focused on the society, Weber concentrated on the individuals and their actions (see structure and action discussion) and whereas Marx argued for the primacy of the material world over the world of ideas, Weber valued ideas as motivating actions of individuals, at least in the big picture.[10][42][43]
Sociology, for Max Weber, is:
...a science which attempts the interpretive understanding of social action in order thereby to arrive at a causal explanation of its course and effects.
Weber was concerned with the question of objectivity and subjectivity.[2] Weber distinguished social action from social behaviour, noting that social action must be understood through how individuals subjectively relate to one another.[2][45] Study of social action through interpretive means (Verstehen) must be based upon understanding the subjective meaning and purpose that the individual attaches to their actions.[2][26] Social actions may have easily identifiable and objective means, but much more subjective ends and the understanding of those ends by a scientist is subject to yet another layer of subjective understanding (that of the scientist).[2] Weber noted that the importance of subjectivity in social sciences makes creation of fool-proof, universal laws much more difficult than in natural sciences and that the amount of objective knowledge that social sciences may achieve is precariously limited.[2] Overall, Weber supported the goal of objective science, but he noted that it is an unreachable goal – although one definitely worth striving for.[2]
There is no absolutely "objective" scientific analysis of culture... All knowledge of cultural reality... is always knowledge from particular points of view. ... an "objective" analysis of cultural events, which proceeds according to the thesis that the ideal of science is the reduction of empirical reality to "laws," is meaningless... [because]... the knowledge of social laws is not knowledge of social reality but is rather one of the various aids used by our minds for attaining this end.
—Max Weber,
"Objectivity" in Social Science, 1897
[46]
The principle of "methodological individualism," which holds that social scientists should seek to understand collectivities (such as nations, cultures, governments, churches, corporations, etc.) solely as the result and the context of the actions of individual persons, can be traced to Weber, particularly to the first chapter of Economy and Society, in which he argues that only individuals "can be treated as agents in a course of subjectively understandable action."[41][45] In other words, Weber argued that social phenomena can be understood scientifically only to the extent that they are captured by models of the behaviour of purposeful individuals, models which Weber called "ideal types," from which actual historical events will necessarily deviate due to accidental and irrational factors.[41] The analytical constructs of an ideal type never exist in reality, but provide objective benchmarks against which real-life constructs can be measured.[47]
Weber's methodology was developed in the context of a wider debate about methodology of social sciences, the Methodenstreit.[26] Weber's position was close to historicism, as he understood social actions as being heavily tied to particular historical contexts and its analysis required the understanding of subjective motivations of individuals (social actors).[26] Thus Weber's methodology emphasises the use of comparative historical analysis.[49] Therefore, Weber was more interested in explaining how a certain outcome was the result of various historical processes rather than predicting an outcome of those processes in the future.[43]
Many scholars have described rationalisation and the question of individual freedom in an increasingly rational society, as the main theme of Weber's work.[2][50][51][52] This theme was situated in the larger context of the relationship between psychological motivations, cultural values and beliefs (primarily, religion) and the structure of the society (usually determined by the economy).[43]
By rationalisation, Weber understood first, the individual cost-benefit calculation, second, the wider, bureaucratic organisation of the organisations and finally, in the more general sense as the opposite of understanding the reality through mystery and magic (disenchantment).[52]
The fate of our times is characterised by rationalisation and intellectualisation and, above all, by the "disenchantment of the world"
Weber began his studies of the subject in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, in which he argued that the redefinition of the connection between work and piety in Protestantism and especially in ascetic Protestant denominations, particularly Calvinism, shifted human effort towards rational efforts aimed at achieving economic gain.[54][55] In Protestant religion, Christian piety towards God was expressed through one's secular vocation (secularisation of calling).[55] The rational roots of this doctrine, he argued, soon grew incompatible with and larger than the religious and so the latter were eventually discarded.[56]
Weber continued his investigation into this matter in later works, notably in his studies on bureaucracy and on the classification of legitimate authority into three types – Rational-legal, traditional and charismatic – of which the legitimate (or rational) is the dominant one in the modern world.[2] In these works Weber described what he saw as society's movement towards rationalisation.[2] Similarly, rationalisation could be seen in the economy, with the development of highly rational and calculating capitalism.[2] Weber also saw rationalisation as one of the main factors setting the European West apart from the rest of the world.[2] Rationalisation relied on deep changes in ethics, religion, psychology and culture; changes that first took place in the Western civilisation.[2]
What Weber depicted was not only the secularisation of Western culture, but also and especially the development of modern societies from the viewpoint of rationalisation. The new structures of society were marked by the differentiation of the two functionally intermeshing systems that had taken shape around the organisational cores of the capitalist enterprise and the bureaucratic state apparatus. Weber understood this process as the institutionalisation of purposive-rational economic and administrative action. To the degree that everyday life was affected by this cultural and societal rationalisation, traditional forms of life – which in the early modern period were differentiated primarily according to one's trade – were dissolved.
Features of rationalisation include increasing knowledge, growing impersonality and enhanced control of social and material life.[2] Weber was ambivalent towards rationalisation; while admitting it was responsible for many advances, in particular, freeing humans from traditional, restrictive and illogical social guidelines, he also criticised it for dehumanising individuals as "cogs in the machine" and curtailing their freedom, trapping them in the bureaucratic iron cage of rationality and bureaucracy.[2][50][57][58] Related to rationalisation is the process of disenchantment, in which the world is becoming more explained and less mystical, moving from polytheistic religions to monotheistic ones and finally to the Godless science of modernity.[2] Those processes affect all of society, removing "sublime values... from public life" and making art less creative.[59]
In a dystopian critique of rationalisation, Weber notes that modern society is a product of an individualistic drive of the Reformation, yet at the same time, the society created in this process is less and less welcoming of individualism.[2]
How is it at all possible to salvage any remnants of 'individual' freedom of movement in any sense given this all-powerful trend?
Weber's work in the field of sociology of religion started with the essay The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism and continued with the analysis of The Religion of China: Confucianism and Taoism, The Religion of India: The Sociology of Hinduism and Buddhism and Ancient Judaism. His work on other religions was interrupted by his sudden death in 1920, which prevented him from following Ancient Judaism with studies of early Christianity and Islam.[60] His three main themes in the essays were the effect of religious ideas on economic activities, the relation between social stratification and religious ideas and the distinguishable characteristics of Western civilization.[61]
Weber saw religion as one of the core forces in the society.[49] His goal was to find reasons for the different development paths of the cultures of the Occident and the Orient, although without judging or valuing them, like some of the contemporary thinkers who followed the social Darwinist paradigm; Weber wanted primarily to explain the distinctive elements of the Western civilisation.[61] In the analysis of his findings, Weber maintained that Calvinist (and more widely, Protestant) religious ideas had had a major impact on the social innovation and development of the economic system of the West, but noted that they were not the only factors in this development. Other notable factors mentioned by Weber included the rationalism of scientific pursuit, merging observation with mathematics, science of scholarship and jurisprudence, rational systematisation and bureaucratisation of government administration and economic enterprise.[61] In the end, the study of the sociology of religion, according to Weber, focused on one distinguishing part of the Western culture, the decline of beliefs in magic, or what he referred to as "disenchantment of the world".[61]
Weber also proposed a socioevolutionary model of religious change, showing that in general, societies have moved from magic to polytheism, then to pantheism, monotheism and finally, ethical monotheism.[62] According to Weber, this evolution occurred as the growing economic stability allowed professionalisation and the evolution of ever more sophisticated priesthood.[63] As societies grew more complex and encompassed different groups, a hierarchy of gods developed and as power in the society became more centralised, the concept of a single, universal God became more popular and desirable.[64]
[edit] The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism
Weber's essay The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism is his most famous work.[30] It is argued that this work should not be viewed as a detailed study of Protestantism, but rather as an introduction into Weber's later works, especially his studies of interaction between various religious ideas and economic behaviour as part of the rationalisation of the economic system.[65] In The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, Weber put forward the thesis that Calvinist ethic and ideas influenced the development of capitalism.[65] He noted the post-Reformation shift of Europe's economic centre away from Catholic countries such as France, Spain and Italy, and toward Protestant countries such as the Netherlands, England, Scotland and Germany. Weber also noted that societies having more Protestants were those with a more highly developed capitalist economy.[66] Similarly, in societies with different religions, most successful business leaders were Protestant.[65] Weber thus argued that Roman Catholicism impeded the development of the capitalist economy in the West, as did other religions such as Confucianism and Buddhism elsewhere in the world.[65]
The development of the concept of the calling quickly gave to the modern entrepreneur a fabulously clear conscience – and also industrious workers; he gave to his employees as the wages of their ascetic devotion to the calling and of co-operation in his ruthless exploitation of them through capitalism the prospect of eternal salvation.
Christian religious devotion had historically been accompanied by rejection of mundane affairs, including economic pursuit.[67] Weber showed that certain types of Protestantism – notably Calvinism – were supportive of rational pursuit of economic gain and worldly activities dedicated to it, seeing them as endowed with moral and spiritual significance.[54] Weber argued that there were many reasons to look for the origins of modern capitalism in the religious ideas of the Reformation.[68] In particular, the Protestant ethic (or more specifically, Calvinist ethic) motivated the believers to work hard, be successful in business and reinvest their profits in further development rather than frivolous pleasures.[65] The notion of calling meant that each individual had to take action in order to be saved; just being a member of the Church was not enough.[55] Predestination also reduced antagonising over economic inequality and further, it meant that a material wealth could be taken as a sign of salvation in the afterlife.[65][69] The believers thus justified pursuit of profit with religion, as instead of being fuelled by morally suspect greed or ambition, their actions were motivated by a highly moral and respected philosophy.[65] This Weber called the "spirit of capitalism": it was the Protestant religious ideology that was behind – and inevitably lead to – the capitalist economic system.[65] This theory is often viewed as a reversal of Marx's thesis that the economic "base" of society determines all other aspects of it.[54]
Weber abandoned research into Protestantism because his colleague Ernst Troeltsch, a professional theologian, had begun work on the book The Social Teachings of the Christian Churches and Sects. Another reason for Weber's decision was that Troeltsch's work already achieved what he desired in that area: laying the groundwork for a comparative analysis of religion and society.[70]
The phrase "work ethic" used in modern commentary is a derivative of the "Protestant ethic" discussed by Weber. It was adopted when the idea of the Protestant ethic was generalised to apply to the Japanese people, Jews and other non-Christians and thus lost its religious connotations.[71]
[edit] The Religion of China: Confucianism and Taoism
The Religion of China: Confucianism and Taoism was Weber's second major work on the sociology of religion. Weber focused on those aspects of Chinese society that were different from those of Western Europe, especially those aspects which contrasted with Puritanism. His work also questioned why capitalism did not develop in China.[72] He focused on the issues of Chinese urban development, Chinese patrimonialism and officialdom and Chinese religion and philosophy (primarily, Confucianism and Taoism), as the areas in which Chinese development differed most distinctively from the European route.[72]
According to Weber, Confucianism and Puritanism are mutually exclusive types of rational thought, each attempting to prescribe a way of life based on religious dogma.[73] Notably, they both valued self control and restraint and did not oppose accumulation of wealth.[73] However, to both those qualities were just means to the final goal and here they were divided by a key difference.[69] Confucianism's goal was "a cultured status position", while Puritanism's goal was to create individuals who are "tools of God".[73] The intensity of belief and enthusiasm for action were rare in Confucianism, but common in Protestantism.[73] Actively working for wealth was unbecoming a proper Confucian.[69] Therefore, Weber states that it was this difference in social attitudes and mentality, shaped by the respective, dominant religions, that contributed to the development of capitalism in the West and the absence of it in China.[73]
[edit] The Religion of India: The Sociology of Hinduism and Buddhism
The Religion of India: The Sociology of Hinduism and Buddhism was Weber's third major work on the sociology of religion. In this work he deals with the structure of Indian society, with the orthodox doctrines of Hinduism and the heterodox doctrines of Buddhism, with modifications brought by the influence of popular religiosity and finally with the impact of religious beliefs on the secular ethic of Indian society.[74] Like Confucianism in China, for Weber, Hinduism in India was a barrier for capitalism.[69] The Indian caste system made it very difficult for individuals to advance in the society beyond their caste.[69] Activity, including economic activity, was seen as unimportant in the context of the advancement of the soul.[69]
Weber ended his research of society and religion in India by bringing in insights from his previous work on China to discuss similarities of the Asian belief systems.[75] He notes that the beliefs saw the meaning of life as otherworldly mystical experience.[75] The social world is fundamentally divided between the educated elite, following the guidance of a prophet or wise man and the uneducated masses whose beliefs are centered on magic.[75] In Asia, there was no Messianic prophecy to give plan and meaning to the everyday life of educated and uneducated alike.[75] Weber juxtaposed such Messianic prophecies (also called ethical prophecies), notably from the Near East region to the exemplary prophecies found on the Asiatic mainland, focused more on reaching to the educated elites and enlightening them on the proper ways to live one's life, usually with little emphasis on hard work and the material world.[75][76] It was those differences that prevented the countries of the Occident from following the paths of the earlier Chinese and Indian civilizations. His next work, Ancient Judaism was an attempt to prove this theory.[75]
[edit] Ancient Judaism
In Ancient Judaism, his fourth major work on the sociology of religion, Weber attempted to explain the factors which resulted in the early differences between Oriental and Occidental religiosity.[77] He contrasted the innerworldly asceticism developed by Western Christianity with mystical contemplation of the kind developed in India.[77] Weber noted that some aspects of Christianity sought to conquer and change the world, rather than withdraw from its imperfections.[77] This fundamental characteristic of Christianity (when compared to Far Eastern religions) stems originally from ancient Jewish prophecy.[78]
Weber noted that Judaism not only fathered Christianity and Islam, but was crucial to the rise of the modern Occidental state; Judaism's influence was as important as Hellenistic and Roman cultures.
Weber's premature death in 1920 prevented him from following his planned analysis of Psalms, the Book of Job, Talmudic Jewry, early Christianity and Islam.
[edit] Economy and Society
In his magnum opus, Economy and Society, Weber distinguished three ideal types of religious attitudes: world-flying mysticism, world-rejecting asceticism, and inner-worldly asceticism. He defined magic as a pre-religious activity.[79]
In political sociology, one of Weber's most significant contributions is his Politics as a Vocation essay. Therein, Weber unveils the definition of the state as that entity which possesses a delegatable monopoly on the legitimate use of physical force.[80] Weber wrote that politics is the sharing of state's power between various groups, and political leaders are those who wield this power.[80] A politician must not be a man of the "true Christian ethic", understood by Weber as being the ethic of the Sermon on the Mount, that is to say, the injunction to turn the other cheek.[81] An adherent of such an ethic ought rather to be understood to be a saint, for it is only saints, according to Weber, that can appropriately follow it.[81] The political realm is no realm for saints; a politician ought to marry the ethic of ultimate ends and the ethic of responsibility and must possess both a passion for his vocation and the capacity to distance himself from the subject of his exertions (the governed).[81]
Weber distinguished three ideal types of political leadership (alternatively referred to as three types of domination, legitimisation or authority):
- charismatic domination (familial and religious),
- traditional domination (patriarchs, patrimonialism, feudalism) and
- legal domination (modern law and state, bureaucracy).[82]
In his view, every historical relation between rulers and ruled contained such elements and they can be analysed on the basis of this tripartite distinction.[83] He notes that the instability of charismatic authority forces it to "routinise" into a more structured form of authority.[57] In a pure type of traditional rule, sufficient resistance to a ruler can lead to a "traditional revolution". The move towards a rational-legal structure of authority, utilising a bureaucratic structure, is inevitable in the end.[84] Thus this theory can be sometimes viewed as part of the social evolutionism theory. This ties to his broader concept of rationalisation by suggesting the inevitability of a move in this direction.[57]
Bureaucratic administration means fundamentally domination through knowledge.
Weber described many ideal types of public administration and government in his masterpiece Economy and Society (1922). His critical study of the bureaucratisation of society became one of the most enduring parts of his work.[57][85] It was Weber who began the studies of bureaucracy and whose works led to the popularisation of this term.[86] Many aspects of modern public administration go back to him and a classic, hierarchically organised civil service of the Continental type is called "Weberian civil service".[87] As the most efficient and rational way of organising, bureaucratisation for Weber was the key part of the rational-legal authority and furthermore, he saw it as the key process in the ongoing rationalisation of the Western society.[57][85]
Weber listed several preconditions for the emergence of the bureaucracy:[88] The growth in space and population being administered, the growth in complexity of the administrative tasks being carried out and the existence of a monetary economy – these resulted in a need for a more efficient administrative system.[88] Development of communication and transportation technologies made more efficient administration possible (and popularly requested) and democratisation and rationalisation of culture resulted in demands that the new system treat everybody equally.[88]
Weber's ideal bureaucracy is characterised by hierarchical organisation, by delineated lines of authority in a fixed area of activity, by action taken (and recorded) on the basis of written rules, by bureaucratic officials needing expert training, by rules being implemented neutrally and by career advancement depending on technical qualifications judged by organisations, not by individuals.[85][88]
The decisive reason for the advance of the bureaucratic organisation has always been its purely technical superiority over any other form of organisation.
While recognising bureaucracy as the most efficient form of organisation and even indispensable for the modern state, Weber also saw it as a threat to individual freedoms and the ongoing bureaucratisation as leading to a "polar night of icy darkness", in which increasing rationalisation of human life traps individuals in the aforementioned "iron cage" of bureaucratic, rule-based, rational control.[85][89] In order to counteract bureaucrats, the system needs entrepreneurs and politicians.[85]
Weber also formulated a three-component theory of stratification, with Social class, Social status and Political party as conceptually distinct elements.[90]
All three dimensions have consequences for what Weber called "life chances" (opportunities to improve one's life).[90]
As part of his overarching effort to understand the unique development of the Western world, Weber produced a detailed general study of the city as the characteristic locus of the social and economic relations, political arrangements, and ideas that eventually came to define the West. This resulted in a monograph titled The City, which was probably compiled from research conducted in 1911-1913, and which was published posthumously in 1921. In 1924 it was incorporated into the second part of his Economy and Society, as chapter XVI, "The City (Non-legitimate Domination)".
According to Weber, the city as a politically autonomous organization of people living in close proximity, employed in a variety of specialized trades, and physically separated from the surrounding countryside, only fully developed in the West and to a great extent shaped its cultural evolution:
The origin of a rational and inner-worldly ethic is associated in the Occident with the appearance of thinkers and prophets [...] who developed in a social context which was alien to the Asiatic cultures. This context consisted of the political problems engendered by the
bourgeois status-group of the city, without which neither Judaism, nor Christianity, nor the development of Hellenistic thinking are conceivable.
Weber argued that Judaism, early Christianity, theology, and later the political party and modern science, were only possible in the urban context that reached a full development the West alone.[92] He also saw in the history of medieval European cities the rise of a unique form of "non-legitimate domination" that successfully challenged the existing forms of legitimate domination (traditional, charismatic, and rational-legal) that had prevailed until then in the Medieval world.[93] This new domination was based on the great economic and military power wielded by the organized community of city-dwellers ("citizens").
Weber regarded himself primarily as a "political economist,"[94][95][96] and all of his professorial appointments were in economics, though today his contributions in that field are largely overshadowed by his role as a founder of modern sociology. As an economist, Weber belonged to the "youngest" German historical school of economics.[97] The great differences between that school's interests and methods on the one hand and those of the neoclassical school (from which modern mainstream economics largely derives) on the other, explain why Weber's influence on economics today is hard to discern.[98]
Though his research interests were always in line with those of the German historicists, with a strong emphasis on interpreting economic history, Weber's defence of "methodological individualism" in the social sciences represented an important break with that school and an embracing of many of the arguments that had been made against the historicists by Carl Menger, the founder of the Austrian School of economics, in the context of the academic Methodenstreit ("debate over methods") of the late 19th century.[41] The phrase "methodological individualism," which has come into common usage in modern debates about the connection between microeconomics and macroeconomics, was coined by the Austrian-American economist Joseph Schumpeter in 1908 as a way of referring to the views of Weber.[41] According to Weber's theses, social research cannot be fully inductive or descriptive, because understanding some phenomenon implies that the researcher must go beyond mere description and interpret it; interpretation requires classification according to abstract "ideal (pure) types".[97] This, together with his antipositivistic argumentation (see Verstehen), can be taken as a methodological justification for the model of the "rational economic man" (homo economicus), which is at the heart of modern mainstream economics.[41][97]
Unlike other historicists, Weber also accepted the marginal theory of value (also called "marginalism") and taught it to his students.[40][99] In 1908, Weber published an article in which he drew a sharp methodological distinction between psychology and economics and attacked the claims that the marginal theory of value in economics reflected the form of the psychological response to stimuli as described by the Weber-Fechner law. Max Weber's article has been cited as a definitive refutation of the dependence of the economic theory of value on the laws of psychophysics by Lionel Robbins, George Stigler,[100] and Friedrich Hayek, though the broader issue of the relation between economics and psychology has come back into the academic debate with the development of "behavioral economics."[101]
Weber's best known work in economics concerned the preconditions for capitalist development, particularly the relations between religion and capitalism, which he explored in The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism as well as in his other works on the sociology of religion.[97] He argued that bureaucratic political and economic systems emerging in the Middle Ages were essential in the rise of modern capitalism (including rational book-keeping and organization of formally free labour), while they were a hindrance in the case of ancient capitalism, which had a different social and political structure based on conquest, slavery, and the coastal city-state.[102] Other contributions include his early work on the economic history of Roman agrarian society (1891) and on the labour relations in Eastern Germany (1892), his analysis of the history of commercial partnerships in the Middle Ages (1889), his critique of Marxism, the discussion of the roles of idealism and materialism in the history of capitalism in his Economy and Society (1922) and his General Economic History (1923), a notable example of the kind of empirical work associated with the German Historical School.[97]
Though today read primarily by sociologists and social philosophers, Weber's work did have a significant influence on Frank Knight, one of the founders of the neoclassical Chicago school of economics, who translated Weber's General Economic History into English in 1927.[103] Knight also wrote in 1956 that Max Weber was the only economist who dealt with the problem of understanding the emergence of modern capitalism "from the angle which alone can yield an answer to such questions, that is, the angle of comparative history in the broad sense."[99]
Weber, like his colleague Werner Sombart, regarded economic calculation and especially the double-entry bookkeeping method of business accounting, as one of the most important forms of rationalisation associated the development of modern capitalism.[104] Weber's preoccupation with the importance of economic calculation led him to develop a critique of socialism as a system that lacked a mechanism for allocating resources efficiently in order to satisfy human needs.[105] Socialist intellectuals like Otto Neurath had realised that in a completely socialised economy, prices would not exist and central planners would have to resort to in-kind (rather than monetary) economic calculation.[105][106] According to Weber, this type of coordination would be inefficient, especially because it would be incapable of solving the problem of imputation (i.e. of accurately determining the relative values of capital goods).[105][106] Weber wrote that, under full socialism,
In order to make possible a rational utilisation of the means of production, a system of in-kind accounting would have to determine "value" – indicators of some kind for the individual capital goods which could take over the role of the "prices" used in book valuation in modern business accounting. But it is not at all clear how such indicators could be established and in particular, verified; whether, for instance, they should vary from one production unit to the next (on the basis of economic location), or whether they should be uniform for the entire economy, on the basis of "social utility," that is, of (present and future) consumption requirements [...] Nothing is gained by assuming that, if only the problem of a non-monetary economy were seriously enough attacked, a suitable accounting method would be discovered or invented. The problem is fundamental to any kind of complete socialisation. We cannot speak of a rational "planned economy" so long as in this decisive respect we have no instrument for elaborating a rational "plan."
This argument against socialism was made independently, at about the same time, by Ludwig von Mises.[105][108] Weber himself had a significant influence on Mises, whom he had befriended when they were both at the University of Vienna in the spring of 1918,[109] and, through Mises, on several other economists associated with the Austrian School in the 20th century.[110] Friedrich Hayek in particular elaborated the arguments of Weber and Mises about economic calculation into a central part of free market economics's intellectual assault on socialism, as well as into a model for the spontaneous coordination of "dispersed knowledge" in markets.[111][112][113]
The prestige of Max Weber among European social scientists would be difficult to over-estimate. He is widely considered the greatest of German sociologists and... has become a leading influence in European and American thought.
Weber's most influential work was on economic sociology, political sociology, and the sociology of religion. Along with Karl Marx and Émile Durkheim,[95] he is commonly regarded as one of the founders of modern sociology. But whereas Durkheim, following Comte, worked in the positivist tradition, Weber was instrumental in developing an antipositivist, hermeneutic, tradition in the social sciences.[114] In this regard he belongs to a similar tradition as his German colleagues Werner Sombart, Georg Simmel, and Wilhelm Dilthey, who stressed the differences between the methodologies appropriate to the social and the natural sciences.[114]
Weber presented sociology as the science of human social action; action which he separated into traditional, affectional, value-rational and instrumental.[115][116]
[Sociology is] the science whose object is to interpret the meaning of social action and thereby give a causal explanation of the way in which the action proceeds and the effects which it produces. By "action" in this definition is meant the human behaviour when and to the extent that the agent or agents see it as subjectively meaningful [...] the meaning to which we refer may be either (a) the meaning actually intended either by an individual agent on a particular historical occasion or by a number of agents on an approximate average in a given set of cases, or (b) the meaning attributed to the agent or agents, as types, in a pure type constructed in the abstract. In neither case is the "meaning" to be thought of as somehow objectively "correct" or "true" by some metaphysical criterion. This is the difference between the empirical sciences of action, such as sociology and history and any kind of a priori discipline, such as jurisprudence, logic, ethics, or aesthetics whose aim is to extract from their subject-matter "correct" or "valid" meaning.
—Max Weber,
The Nature of Social Action, 1922,
[117]
In his own time, however, Weber was viewed primarily as a historian and an economist.[95][96] The breadth of Weber's topical interests is apparent in the depth of his social theory:
The affinity between capitalism and Protestantism, the religious origins of the Western world, the force of charisma in religion as well as in politics, the all-embracing process of rationalisation and the bureaucratic price of progress, the role of legitimacy and of violence as the offspring of leadership, the 'disenchantment' of the modern world together with the never-ending power of religion, the antagonistic relation between intellectualism and eroticism: all these are key concepts which attest to the enduring fascination of Weber's thinking.
Many of Weber's works famous today were collected, revised and published posthumously. Significant interpretations of his writings were produced by such sociological luminaries as Talcott Parsons and C. Wright Mills. Parsons in particular imparted to Weber's works a functionalist, teleological perspective; this personal interpretation has been criticised for a latent conservatism.[119]
Weber has influenced many later social theorists, such as Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, György Lukács and Jürgen Habermas.[2] Different elements of his thought were emphasized by Carl Schmitt, Joseph Schumpeter, Leo Strauss, Hans Morgenthau, and Raymond Aron.[2] According to Austrian economist Ludwig von Mises, who had met Weber during his time at the University of Vienna,
The early death of this genius was a great disaster for Germany. Had Weber lived longer, the German people of today would be able to look to this example of an "
Aryan" who would not be broken by
National Socialism.
Weber's friend, the psychiatrist and existentialist philosopher Karl Jaspers, described him "the greatest German of our era" and his untimely death felt to Jaspers "as if the German world had lost its heart."[121]
Weber's explanations are highly specific to the historical periods he analysed.[122] This makes it more difficult to generalise from his analysis and modify his theories for other circumstances.[122]
Many scholars, however, have disagreed with specific claims Weber makes in his historical analysis. For example, the economist Joseph Schumpeter argued that capitalism did not begin with the Industrial Revolution but in 14th century Italy.[123] In Milan, Venice and Florence the small city-state governments led to the development of the earliest forms of capitalism.[124] In the 16th century Antwerp was a commercial centre of Europe. Also, the predominantly Calvinist country of Scotland did not enjoy the same economic growth as the Netherlands, England and New England. It has been pointed out that the Netherlands, which had a Calvinist majority, industrialised much later in the 19th century than predominantly Catholic Belgium, which was one of the centres of the Industrial Revolution on the European mainland.[125] Emil Kauder expanded Schumpeter's argument by arguing the hypothesis that Calvinism hurt the development of capitalism by leading to the development of the labour theory of value.[126]
Weber wrote his books in German. Original titles printed after his death (1920) are most likely compilations of his unfinished works (of the 'Collected Essays...' form). Many translations are made of parts or sections of various German originals and the names of the translations often do not reveal what part of German work they contain. Weber's work is generally quoted according to the critical Gesamtausgabe (collected works edition), which is published by Mohr Siebeck in Tübingen. For an extensive list of Max Weber's works see list of Max Weber works.
- ^ "Max Weber." Encyclopædia Britannica. 2009. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. 20 April 2009. Britannica.com
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u v w x y z aa ab ac ad ae af ag ah ai aj ak al am an ao ap aq ar as at au av aw ax Kim, Sung Ho (24 August 2007). "Max Weber". Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/weber/. Retrieved 17 February 2010.
- ^ a b Max Weber; Hans Heinrich Gerth; Bryan S. Turner (7 March 1991). From Max Weber: essays in sociology. Psychology Press. p. 1. ISBN 978-0-415-06056-1. http://books.google.com/books?id=Y_pqZS5q72UC&pg=PR1. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Radkau, Joachim and Patrick Ca miller. (2009). Max Weber: A Biography. Trans. Patrick Ca miller. Polity Press. (ISBN 9780745641478)
- ^ a b Habermas, Jürgen, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity, Polity Press (1985), ISBN 0-7456-0830-2, p2
- ^ Macionis, John J. (2012). Sociology 14th Edition. Boston: Pearson. p. 88. ISBN 978-0-205-11671-3.
- ^ Weber, Max The Protestant Ethic and "The Spirit of Capitalism" (1905). Translated by Stephen Kalberg (2002), Roxbury Publishing Company, pp. 19, 35; Weber's references on these pages to "Superstructure" and "base" are unambiguous references to Marxism's base/superstructure theory.
- ^ Periodical, Sociology Volume 250, September 1999, 'Max Weber'
- ^ Sica, Alan (2004). Max Weber and the New Century. London: Transaction Publishers, p. 24. ISBN 0-7658-0190-6.
- ^ a b c d e f g Craig J. Calhoun (2002). Classical sociological theory. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 165. ISBN 978-0-631-21348-2. http://books.google.com/books?id=6mq-H3EcUx8C&pg=PA165. Retrieved 19 March 2011.
- ^ a b Dirk Käsler (1988). Max Weber: an introduction to his life and work. University of Chicago Press. p. 2. ISBN 978-0-226-42560-3. http://books.google.com/books?id=v915AC-dflsC&pg=PA2. Retrieved 24 March 2011.
- ^ a b George Ritzer (29 September 2009). Contemporary Sociological Theory and Its Classical Roots: The Basics. McGraw-Hill. p. 32. ISBN 978-0-07-340438-7. http://books.google.com/books?id=pX6pPwAACAAJ. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ a b c Lutz Kaelber Max Weber’s Personal Life, 1886–1893
- ^ a b Bendix, Reinhard (1 July 1977). Max Weber: An Intellectual Portrait. University of California Press. p. 1. ISBN 0-520-03194-6. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA1&lpg=PA1.
- ^ a b Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 146. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ a b Lutz Kaelber, Max Weber's Dissertation
- ^ a b c d Bendix (1977). Max Weber. p. 2. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA2&lpg=PA2.
- ^ a b c d e Ludwig M. Lachmann (1970). The legacy of Max Weber. Ludwig von Mises Institute. p. 143. ISBN 978-1-61016-072-8. http://books.google.com/books?id=pxAlydwrvcAC&pg=PA143. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ a b Gianfranco Poggi (2006). Weber: a short introduction. Polity. p. 5. ISBN 978-0-7456-3489-0. http://books.google.com/books?id=c5a2LWRh7uEC&pg=PA5. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Wolfgang Justin Mommsen (1984). Max Weber and German Politics, 1890–1920. University of Chicago Press. p. 19. ISBN 0-226-53399-9.
- ^ Wolfgang J. Mommsen; Michael Steinberg (25 July 1990). Max Weber and German Politics, 1890–1920. University of Chicago Press. pp. 54–56. ISBN 978-0-226-53399-5. http://books.google.com/books?id=a99RC3rJoIgC&pg=PA54. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Eric J. Hobsbawm (1987). The age of empire, 1875–1914. Pantheon Books. p. 152. ISBN 978-0-394-56319-0. http://books.google.com/books?id=Xc4NAQAAMAAJ. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Marianne Weber. Last accessed on 18 September 2006. Based on Lengermann, P., & Niebrugge-Brantley, J.(1998). The Women Founders: Sociology and Social Theory 1830–1930. New York: McGraw-Hill.
- ^ Hartmut Lehmann; Guenther Roth (29 September 1995). Weber's Protestant Ethic: Origins, Evidence, Contexts. Cambridge University Press. p. 95. ISBN 978-0-521-55829-7. http://books.google.com/books?id=HF3jdg0peNYC&pg=PA95. Retrieved 24 March 2011.
- ^ Paul Honigsheim; Alan Sica (2003). The unknown Max Weber. Transaction Publishers. p. 86. ISBN 978-0-7658-0953-7. http://books.google.com/books?id=YoHSBnN9DY4C&pg=PA86. Retrieved 24 March 2011.
- ^ a b c d e Craig J. Calhoun (2002). Classical sociological theory. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 166. ISBN 978-0-631-21348-2. http://books.google.com/books?id=6mq-H3EcUx8C&pg=PA166. Retrieved 19 March 2011.
- ^ Max Weber; Richard Swedberg (1999). Essays in economic sociology. Princeton University Press. p. 7. ISBN 978-0-691-00906-3. http://books.google.com/books?id=WaV7Q35jy_AC&pg=PA7. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ a b c d e Bendix (1977). Max Weber. p. 3. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA3&lpg=PA2.
- ^ Guenther Roth: "History and sociology in the work of Max Weber", in: British Journal of Sociology, 27(3), 1979
- ^ a b Max Weber; Richard Swedberg (1999). Essays in economic sociology. Princeton University Press. p. 22. ISBN 978-0-691-00906-3. http://books.google.com/books?id=WaV7Q35jy_AC&pg=PA22. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Iannaccone, Laurence (1998). "Introduction to the Economics of Religion". Journal of Economic Literature 36, 1465–1496.
- ^ a b c Wolfgang J. Mommsen, The Political and Social Theory of Max Weber, University of Chicago Press, 1992, ISBN 0-226-53400-6, Google Print, p.81, p. 60, p. 327
- ^ a b c Kaesler, Dirk (1989). Max Weber: An Introduction to His Life and Work. University of Chicago Press, p. 18. ISBN 0-226-42560-6
- ^ Gerth, H.H. and C. Wright Mills (1948). From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. London: Routledge (UK), ISBN 0-415-17503-8
- ^ Sven Eliaeson, "Constitutional Caesarism: Weber's Politics in their German Context," in Turner, Stephen (ed) (2000). The Cambridge Companion to Weber. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 142.
- ^ P. G. C. van Schie; Gerrit Voermann (2006). The dividing line between success and failure: a comparison of liberalism in the Netherlands and Germany in the 19th and 20th centuries. LIT Verlag Münster. p. 64. ISBN 978-3-8258-7668-5. http://books.google.com/books?id=PWFMt03C6h0C&pg=PA64. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ David Frisby, Georg Simmel (Key Sociologists), 2nd ed., (Routledge, London), 2002. ISBN 0-415-28535-6.
- ^ H. H. Gerth and C. W. Mills, "A Biographical View, in From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology.
- ^ Alan Mittleman, "Leo Strauss and Relativism: the Critique of Max Weber," Religion, 29, pp. 15-27.
- ^ a b Richard Swedberg, "Max Weber as an Economist and as a Sociologist: Towards a Fuller Understanding of Weber's View of Economics - Critical Essay," American Journal of Economics and Sociology, (1999).
- ^ a b c d e f "Methodological individualism," Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, accessed 30 Jan. 2010
- ^ Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 144. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ a b c Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 148. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ Robert B. Denhardt (2 March 2010). Theories of Public Organization. Cengage Learning. p. 27. ISBN 978-1-4390-8623-0. http://books.google.com/books?id=0mt5MF9EBJgC&pg=PA27. Retrieved 14 April 2011.
- ^ a b George Ritzer (29 September 2009). Contemporary Sociological Theory and Its Classical Roots: The Basics. McGraw-Hill. p. 31. ISBN 978-0-07-340438-7. http://books.google.com/books?id=pX6pPwAACAAJ. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Max Weber, Sociological Writings, Excerpts
- ^ Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 149. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ Quoted in Roth, Guenther and Claus Wittich. 1978. Economy and Society: an outline of interpretive sociology. University of California Press, Google Print, p. xxxiii
- ^ a b Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 153. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ a b Craig J. Calhoun (2002). Classical sociological theory. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 167. ISBN 978-0-631-21348-2. http://books.google.com/books?id=6mq-H3EcUx8C&pg=PA166. Retrieved 19 March 2011.
- ^ George Ritzer (29 September 2009). Contemporary Sociological Theory and Its Classical Roots: The Basics. McGraw-Hill. p. 30. ISBN 978-0-07-340438-7. http://books.google.com/books?id=pX6pPwAACAAJ. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ a b Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 151. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ Basit Bilal Koshul (2005). The postmodern significance of Max Weber's legacy: disenchanting disenchantment. Macmillan. p. 11. ISBN 978-1-4039-6784-8. http://books.google.com/books?id=BZwEI-o3PCIC&pg=PA11. Retrieved 23 March 2011.
- ^ a b c Bendix (1977). Max Weber. pp. 60–61. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA60&lpg=PA60&vq=Calvinism.
- ^ a b c d Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 162. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ Andrew J. Weigert (July 1991). Mixed emotions: certain steps toward understanding ambivalence. SUNY Press. p. 110. ISBN 978-0-7914-0600-7. http://books.google.com/books?id=uH0srBp2W4YC&pg=PA110. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ a b c d e George Ritzer (29 September 2009). Contemporary Sociological Theory and Its Classical Roots: The Basics. McGraw-Hill. pp. 38–42. ISBN 978-0-07-340438-7. http://books.google.com/books?id=pX6pPwAACAAJ. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 177. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. pp. 151–152. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ Bendix (1977). Max Weber. p. 285. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA285&lpg=PA285.
- ^ a b c d Bendix (1977). "IX: Basic Concepts of Political Sociology". Max Weber. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA285&lpg=PA285.
- ^ Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 154. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 155. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. p. 158. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ a b c d e f g h George Ritzer (29 September 2009). Contemporary Sociological Theory and Its Classical Roots: The Basics. McGraw-Hill. pp. 35–37. ISBN 978-0-07-340438-7. http://books.google.com/books?id=pX6pPwAACAAJ. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Weber The Protestant Ethic..., pp. 15–16
- ^ Bendix (1977). Max Weber. p. 57. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA57&lpg=PA57&vq=mundane+affairs.
- ^ Bendix. Max Weber. p. 54.
- ^ a b c d e f George Ritzer (29 September 2009). Contemporary Sociological Theory and Its Classical Roots: The Basics. McGraw-Hill. pp. 37–38. ISBN 978-0-07-340438-7. http://books.google.com/books?id=pX6pPwAACAAJ. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Bendix (1977). Max Weber. p. 49. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA49&lpg=PA49.
- ^ Richard Swedberg; Ola Agevall (2005). The Max Weber dictionary: key words and central concepts. Stanford University Press. p. 310. ISBN 978-0-8047-5095-0. http://books.google.com/books?id=_c3Mcnh8hCgC&pg=PA310. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ a b Bendix (1977). Max Weber. pp. 98–99. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA98&lpg=PA98.
- ^ a b c d e Bendix (1977). Max Weber. pp. 135–141. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA135&lpg=PA135.
- ^ Bendix (1977). Max Weber. pp. 142–158. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA142&lpg=PA142.
- ^ a b c d e f Bendix (1977). Max Weber. p. 199. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA199&lpg=PA199.
- ^ Reinhard Bendix (1977). Max Weber: an intellectual portrait. University of California Press. p. 90. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/books?id=65IUL-VaFGsC&pg=PA90. Retrieved 5 April 2011.
- ^ a b c Bendix (1977). Max Weber. pp. 200–201. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA200&lpg=PA200.
- ^ Bendix (1977). Max Weber. pp. 204–205. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA204&lpg=PA204.
- ^ Pawel Zaleski "Ideal Types in Max Weber’s Sociology of Religion: Some Theoretical Inspirations for a Study of the Religious Field", Polish Sociological Review No. 3(171)/2010
- ^ a b Daniel Warner (1991). An ethic of responsibility in international relations. Lynne Rienner Publishers. pp. 9–10. ISBN 978-1-55587-266-3. http://books.google.com/books?id=jNc4mc_MYdIC&pg=PA9. Retrieved 5 April 2011.
- ^ a b c Randal Marlin (2002). Propaganda and the ethics of persuasion. Broadview Press. p. 155. ISBN 978-1-55111-376-0. http://books.google.com/books?id=Zp38Ot2g7LEC&pg=PA155. Retrieved 5 April 2011.
- ^ Wolfgang J. Mommsen (1992). The Political and Social Theory of Max Weber: Collected Essays. University of Chicago Press. p. 46. ISBN 978-0-226-53400-8. http://books.google.com/books?id=kgF9bjMoocYC&pg=PA46. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Bendix (1977). Max Weber. p. 296. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA296&lpg=PA296.
- ^ Bendix (1998-11). Max Weber. pp. 303–305. ISBN 978-0-415-17453-4. http://books.google.com/?id=C_j_2nOUIpcC&pg=PA303&lpg=PA303.
- ^ a b c d e f Richard Swedberg; Ola Agevall (2005). The Max Weber dictionary: key words and central concepts. Stanford University Press. pp. 18–21. ISBN 978-0-8047-5095-0. http://books.google.com/books?id=_c3Mcnh8hCgC&pg=PA19. Retrieved 23 March 2011.
- ^ Marshall Sashkin; Molly G. Sashkin (28 January 2003). Leadership that matters: the critical factors for making a difference in people's lives and organisations' success. Berrett-Koehler Publishers. p. 52. ISBN 978-1-57675-193-0. http://books.google.com/books?id=q12zbgs-jyYC&pg=PA52. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ a b Liesbet Hooghe (2001). The European Commission and the integration of Europe: images of governance. Cambridge University Press. p. 40. ISBN 978-0-521-00143-4. http://books.google.com/books?id=e15KnRiGipYC&pg=PA40. Retrieved 23 March 2011.
- ^ a b c d Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. pp. 172–176. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ George Ritzer, Enchanting a Disenchanted World: Revolutionizing the Means of Consumption, Pine Forge Press, 2004, ISBN 0-7619-8819-X, Google Print, p.55
- ^ a b Bendix (1977). Max Weber. pp. 85–87. ISBN 978-0-520-03194-4. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA85&lpg=PA85.
- ^ Quoted in Bendix, Reinhard (1 July 1977). Max Weber: An Intellectual Portrait. University of California Press. p. 79. ISBN 0-520-03194-6. http://books.google.com/?id=63sC9uaYqQsC&pg=PA1&lpg=PA79.
- ^ Richard Swedberg; Ola Agevall (2005). The Max Weber dictionary: key words and central concepts. Stanford University Press. pp. 283. ISBN 978-0-8047-5095-0. http://books.google.com/books?id=_c3Mcnh8hCgC&pg=PA283. Retrieved 30 October 2011.
- ^ Richard Swedberg; Ola Agevall (2005). The Max Weber dictionary: key words and central concepts. Stanford University Press. pp. 64–65. ISBN 978-0-8047-5095-0. http://books.google.com/books?id=_c3Mcnh8hCgC&pg=PA64. Retrieved 30 October 2011.
- ^ M. Weber, "Science as a Vocation", lecture given in 1918 at Munich University
- ^ a b c William Petersen, Against the Stream, Transaction Publishers, ISBN 0-7658-0222-8, 2004, Google Print, p.24
- ^ a b Peter R. Baehr, Founders Classics Canons, Transaction Publishers, 2002, ISBN 0-7658-0129-9, Google Print, p.22
- ^ a b c d e Max Weber, 1864–1920, New School for Social Research
- ^ "The German Historical School", New School for Social Research
- ^ a b Arthur Schweitzer, "Frank Knight's Social Economics," History of Political Economics, 7, 279-292 (1975).
- ^ George Stigler, "The Development of Utility Theory. Ii", The Journal of Political Economy 58, 373 (1950).
- ^ Harro Mass, "Disciplining Boundaries: Lionel Robbins, Max Weber, and the Borderlands of Economics, History, and Psychology," Journal of the History of Economic Thought 31, 500 (2009).
- ^ Weber, Max. Selections in Translation. Trans. Eric Matthews. Ed. W. G. Runciman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. "Urbanisation and Social Structure in the Ancient World," pg. 290-314.
- ^ Ross B. Emmett (2005). Frank Knight and the Chicago School in American Economics. Routledge. pp. 111–123. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/97804157750070|97804157750070]]. http://books.google.com/books?id=h0iLWOEln-EC&pg=PA111. Retrieved 1 April 2011.
- ^ Richard Swedberg; Ola Agevall (2005). The Max Weber dictionary: key words and central concepts. Stanford University Press. pp. 22–23. ISBN 978-0-8047-5095-0. http://books.google.com/books?id=_c3Mcnh8hCgC&pg=PA22. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ a b c d Keith Tribe (1995). Strategies of Economic Order: German Economic Discourse, 1750–1950. Cambridge University Press. pp. 140–168. ISBN 978-0-521-61943-1. http://books.google.com/books?id=Y3Z4V9A8LzoC&pg=PA140. Retrieved 30 March 2011.
- ^ a b Jordi Cat, "Political Economy: Theory, Practice, and Philosophical Consequences", supplement to "Otto Neurath," Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2010 Edition).
- ^ Max Weber, Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich, eds. (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), vol. I, ch. 2., sec. 12, pp. 100–03.
- ^ Jörg Guido Hülsmann (1995). Mises: The Last Knight of Liberalism. Ludwig von Mises Institute. pp. 392–396. ISBN 1-933550-18-X. http://mises.org/books/lastknight.pdf. Retrieved 30 March 2011.
- ^ F. A. Hayek, Introduction to Mises's Memoirs, pp. xvi–xvii (1977).
- ^ "Between Mises and Keynes: An Interview with Gottfried von Haberler (1900–1995), The Austrian Economics Newsletter, 20(1), 2000. Mises.org
- ^ Friedrich Hayek, "Socialist Calculation", in Individualism and Economic Order, (University of Chicago Press, 1948).
- ^ Interview with F. A. Hayek, 1985
- ^ Press release, Nobel Memorial Prize in Economics for 1974.
- ^ a b John K. Rhoads, Critical Issues in Social Theory, Penn State Press, 1991, ISBN 0-271-00753-2, Google Print, p.40
- ^ Joan Ferrante, Sociology: A Global Perspective, Thomson Wadsworth, 2005, ISBN 0-495-00561-4, Google Print, p.21
- ^ George Ritzer (29 September 2009). Contemporary Sociological Theory and Its Classical Roots: The Basics. McGraw-Hill. p. 33. ISBN 978-0-07-340438-7. http://books.google.com/books?id=pX6pPwAACAAJ. Retrieved 22 March 2011.
- ^ Weber, Max The Nature of Social Action, in Runciman, W.G., Weber: Selections in Translation, Cambridge University Press, 1991. p. 7.
- ^ Radkau, Joachim Max Weber: A Biography. 1995. Polity Press. (Inside sleeve)
- ^ Fish, Jonathan S. 2005. 'Defending the Durkheimian Tradition. Religion, Emotion and Morality' Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing.
- ^ Ludwig von Mises, Memoirs, (Mises Institute, Auburn, AL, 2009), p. 88.
- ^ Quoted in Peter Baehr, "The Grammar of Prudence: Arendt, Jaspers and the Appraisal of Max Weber," in Hannah Arendt in Jerusalem, edited by Steven E. Aschheim (University of California Press, 2001), p. 410.
- ^ a b Kenneth Allan; Kenneth D. Allan (2 November 2005). Explorations in Classical Sociological Theory: Seeing the Social World. Pine Forge Press. pp. 150–151. ISBN [[Special:BookSources/978-1-4120-5927-9|978-1-4120-5927-9]].
- ^ Schumpeter, Joseph: "History of Economic Analysis", Oxford University Press, 1954
- ^ Rothbard, Muarry N.: "Economic Thought Before Adam Smith", Ludwig von Mises Press, 1995, p. 142
- ^ Evans, Eric J.: "The Forging of the Modern State: Early Industrial Britain, 1783–1870", Longman, 1983, p. 114, ISBN 0-582-48969-5.
- ^ Kauder, Emil: "The Retarded Acceptance of the Marginal Utility Theory", Quarterly Journal of Economics 67(4), 1953
- Ankerl, Guy (1972) (in French). Sociologues allemands. Avec le dictionnaire de "l'Ethique protestante et l'esprit du capitalisme" de Max Weber. Neuchâtel:: A la Baconnière..
- Bruun, Hans Henrik (2007). Rethinking classical sociology.. Aldershot, Ashgate. p. 298. http://www.amazon.com/gp/reader/0754645290 Science, values, and politics in Max Weber's methodology.
- Green, Robert, ed. (1959). Problems in European Civilization, Protestantism and Capitalism: The Weber Thesis and Its Critics. Boston: Heath.
- Haidenko, Piama; Translated by H. Campbell Creighton, M.A. (Oxon) (1989). "The Sociology of Max Weber". In Kon, Igor (DOC, DjVu). A History of Classical Sociology. Moscow: Progress Publishers. pp. 255–311. ISBN 5-01-001102-6. http://su-ltd.mylivepage.ru/file/2715/6547_Kon_History_of_Classical_Sociology.zip.
- Korotayev, Andrey; Malkov, A.; Khaltourina, D. (2006). "Chapter 6: Reconsidering Weber: Literacy and "the Spirit of Capitalism"" (Google Books). Introduction to Social Macrodynamics. Moscow: URSS. ISBN 5-484-00414-4. http://books.google.com/?id=tyoryrjrzUMC&printsec=frontcover&dq=isbn:5484004144#v=onepage&q&f=false.
- Mitzman, Arthur (1985) [1970]. The Iron Cage: An Historical Interpretation of Max Weber. New Brunswick NJ: Transaction Books. ISBN 0-87855-984-1.
- Marra, Realino (1992), Dalla comunità al diritto moderno. La formazione giuridica di Max Weber. 1882-1889, Giappichelli, Torino
- Marra, Realino (1995), La libertà degli ultimi uomini. Studi sul pensiero giuridico e politico di Max Weber, Giappichelli, Torino
- Marra, Realino (2002), Capitalismo e anticapitalismo in Max Weber. Storia di Roma e sociologia del diritto nella genesi dell’opera weberiana, il Mulino, Bologna
- Quensel, Bernhard K. (2007), Max Webers Konstruktionslogik. Sozialökonomik zwischen Geschichte und Theorie, Nomos, ISBN 978-3-8329-2517-8 [Revisiting Weber's concept of sociology against the background of his juristic and economic provenance within the framework of "social economics"]
- Radkau, Joachim (2005), Max Weber [The most important Weber biography on Max Weber's life and torments since Marianne Weber.]
- Radkau, Joachim (2005/2009). Max Weber: A Biography. Translated into English by Patrick Camiller. Polity Press. ISBN 978-0-7456-4147-8
- Ritzer, George, ed. (1996). "Sociological Theory". Max Weber (fourth ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill. ISBN 0-07-114660-1.
- Roth, Guenther: (2001), Max Webers deutsch-englische Familiengeschichte, J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), ISBN 3-16-147557-7
- Lawrence A. Scaff: Max Weber in America, Princeton University Press, Princeton/Oxford, England 2011 ISBN 978-0-691-14779-6
- Shils, Edward and Rheinstein, Max: (1964) Max Weber Law in Economy and Society, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, ISBN 0-674-55651-8; ISBN 0-674-55651-8; ISBN 978-0-674-55651-5.
- Stapelfeldt, Gerhard (2004) (in German). Kritik der ökonomischen Rationalität.
- Swatos, William H., ed. (1990). Time, Place, and Circumstance: Neo-Weberian Studies in Comparative Religious History. New York: Greenwood Press. ISBN 0-313-26892-4.
- Swedberg, Richard (1998). Max Weber and the Idea of Economic Sociology. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-07013-X.
- Swedberg, Richard (October 1999). "Max Weber as an Economist and as a Sociologist". American Journal of Economics and Sociology. http://articles.findarticles.com/p/articles/mi_m0254/is_4_58/ai_58496750.
- Weber, Marianne (1988) [1926]. Max Weber: A Biography. New Brunswick: Transaction Books. ISBN 0-471-92333-8.
Texts of his works:
Analysis of his works:
Persondata |
Name |
Weber, Maximilian |
Alternative names |
Weber, Max |
Short description |
Founder of modern sociology |
Date of birth |
(1864-04-21)21 April 1864 |
Place of birth |
Erfurt, Germany |
Date of death |
14 June 1920(1920-06-14) |
Place of death |
Munich, Germany |