Pericles, son of Xanthippus, Athenian  AUSTRO-ATHENIAN EMPIRE: Roderick T. Long's Web Journal

(Formerly: In a Blog’s Stead.)   
When you tire of my blog, go to my homepage or check out my links.

WARNING: This website is not in compliance with the requirements of Mirari Vos.
Truth forever on the scaffold,
Wrong forever on the throne.

– James Russell Lowell
A political battle is merely a skirmish fought with muskets;
a philosophical battle is a nuclear war.

– Ayn Rand
Facts must yield to ideas.
Peaceably and patiently if possible.
Violently if not.

– Lord Acton


 Roderick T. Long  BUY MY BOOK OR ELSE!

DON’T PANIC!!!

That brilliant post you’re looking for
is archived here.



      

   

   


Good-bye Forever

My blog is moving to a new location! The new address is praxeology.net/blog and the new RSS feed is praxeology.net/blog/feed.

Barring unforeseen problems with the new version, this will be my last post here at the old. Old posts will continue to be archived here, but new ones will be archived at the new version. So good-bye, but only sort of.

Posted August 31st, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog08-06.htm#06
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Journalist Grows Spine!

Keith Olbermann brings it:

Mr. Rumsfeld’s remarkable comments to the Veterans of Foreign Wars yesterday demand the deep analysis and the sober contemplation of every American. For they do not merely serve to impugn the morality or intelligence, indeed the loyalty, of the majority of Americans who oppose the transient occupants of the highest offices in the land. Worse still, they credit those same transient occupants – our employees – with a total omniscience; a total omniscience which neither common sense, nor this administration’s track record at home or abroad, suggests they deserve. ...

That about which Mr. Rumsfeld is confused is simply this: this is a democracy. Still. Sometimes just barely. And as such, all voices count, not just his. Had he or his President perhaps proven any of their prior claims of omniscience – about Osama Bin Laden’s plans five years ago; about Saddam Hussein’s weapons four years ago; about Hurricane Katrina’s impact one year ago – we all might be able to swallow hard, and accept their omniscience as a bearable, even useful, recipe of fact plus ego. But to date this government has proved little besides its own arrogance and its own hubris. Mr. Rumsfeld is also personally confused, morally or intellectually, about his own standing in this matter. From Iraq to Katrina, to the entire fog of fear which continues to envelop this nation – he, Mr. Bush, Mr. Cheney, and their cronies, have inadvertently or intentionally profited and benefited, both personally and politically. And yet he can stand up in public and question the morality and the intellect of those of us who dare ask just for the receipt for the Emperor’s New Clothes. In what country was Mr. Rumsfeld raised? As a child, of whose heroism did he read? On what side of the battle for freedom did he dream one day to fight? With what country has he confused the United States of America? ... The confusion is about whether this Secretary of Defense, and this administration, are in fact now accomplishing what they claim the terrorists seek: the destruction of our freedoms, the very ones for which the same veterans Mr. Rumsfeld addressed yesterday in Salt Lake City so valiantly fought. ...

And about Mr. Rumsfeld’s other main assertion, that this country faces a “new type of fascism”? As he was correct to remind us how a government that knew everything could get everything wrong, so too was he right when he said that – though probably not in the way he thought he meant it.

Read the rest of Olbermann’s response to Rumsfeld’s speech. Better yet, watch the video. (For some reason I can’t link to it from this page, but you can get it here.) Olbermann’s historical digression on Chamberlain and Churchill is, alas, mostly mistaken,* but the rest of it is great stuff.


* Olbermann, like Rumsfeld, buys into the old myth that Neville Chamberlain was naïve about Hitler’s intentions. In fact Chamberlain was perfectly aware how dangerous Hitler was – but he was also aware how poorly prepared the British military was, and so was quite sensibly unwilling to challenge Hitler until he had first built up Britain’s military power – which he directly proceeded to do. It’s been said that diplomacy is the art of saying “nice doggie” while looking for a rock – which is a pretty good description of what Chamberlain was doing. Churchill’s plan for immediate confrontation, by contrast, was like attacking the dog barehanded while hoping that someone else with a rock will happen along. The prospects for success of Churchill’s policy depended crucially on American entry into the war; otherwise it was suicidal. Since America did ultimately enter the war, Churchill’s policy may look sensible in hindsight, but given the antiwar sentiment in the U.S. at the time it was hardly something that could reasonably be counted on. Churchill gambled with his country’s freedom and got lucky.

Posted August 31st, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog08-06.htm#05
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Beirut Update

Today I’m pleased and relieved to learn that my friends Jeremy and Lucy Koons made it out of Lebanon safely during the recent unpleasantness.

I hope to get back to more regular blogging soon – things have just been über-hectic here of late.

Posted August 23rd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog08-06.htm#04
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Tuscaloosa Countdown

Deadlines are looming for the Alabama Philosophical Society conference:

See the APS website for more info.

Also, undergrads – don’t forget the student essay contest.

Posted August 23rd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog08-06.htm#03
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Anarchy in D.C.

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

The Molinari Society will be holding its third annual Symposium in conjunction with the Eastern Division of the American Philosophical Association in Mordor, I mean Washington DC, December 27-30, 2006. Here’s the latest schedule info:

GVIII-4. Friday, 29 December 2006, 11:15 a.m.-1:15 p.m.
Molinari Society symposium: “Anarchist Perspectives”
Virginia Suite C (Lobby Level), Marriott Wardman Park Hotel, 2660 Woodley Road NW

Session 1, 11:15-12:15:
chair: Roderick T. Long (Auburn University)
speaker: Matthew MacKenzie (Muhlenberg College)
title: “Exploitation: A Dialectical Anarchist Perspective”
commentator: Charles W. Johnson (Molinari Institute)

Session 2, 12:15-1:15:
chair: Roderick T. Long (Auburn University)
speaker: Geoffrey Allan Plauché (Louisiana State University)
title: “On the Myth of the Founder-Legislator in Political Philosophy”
commentator: Charles W. Johnson (Molinari Institute)

Posted August 3rd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog08-06.htm#02
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


JLS 20.2: What Lies Within?

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

The latest issue (20.2) of the Journal of Libertarian Studies is out. Catch the action:

Valentin Petkantchin argues that Adam Smith’s “third duty of the sovereign” is less interventionist than traditionally thought; B. K. Marcus defends the privatisation of the airwaves; Bob Murphy and Gene Callahan challenge Hans Hoppe’s argumentation ethic; Jeff Hummel criticises Tom Woods’ take on American history; Sam Bostaph praises Tom Woods’ account of the Catholic Church’s relationship to Progressivism and to Austrian economics; and Rob Bass critiques Tibor Machan’s book on Ayn Rand.

Read a fuller summary of 20.2’s contents here.

Read the articles themselves (already online) here.

Read summaries of previous issues under my editorship here.

Read back issues online here.

Subscribe here.

Posted August 3rd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog08-06.htm#01
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Feel the Irony

As everyone on Earth now knows, our Prince President was recently recorded saying: “See, the irony is, what they need to do is get Syria to get Hezbollah to stop doing this shit.”

But everybody’s been focusing on the wrong word. What’s objectionable in this sentence is not the word “shit” but the word “irony.” What exactly is supposed to be ironic about the situation?

Well, maybe it’s kind of like a black fly in your Chardonnay.

Posted July 29th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#12
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Victory Through Victim-Swapping

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

By most reports, Israeli bombings of Lebanon are strengthening Hezbollah’s support among Lebanese civilians, while Hezbollah bombings of Israel are strengthening the Israeli government’s support among Israeli civilians.

So here we have (what are by libertarian standards) two criminal gangs, both blasting away at innocent civilians, and the result is to increase these gangs’ popularity among the civilians being victimised! A very successful outcome for both sides.

The trick, of course, is that each gang is blasting away at civilians in the other gang’s territory. If each gang were to attack its own civilians directly, those civilians would quickly turn against the gangs in their midst. But since in fact each side’s continuation of bombings is what allows the other side to excuse, and get away with, its bombings, the situation isn’t really all that different; each side is causing its own civilians to be bombed. It’s just that by following the stratagem of attacking each other’s civilians, the two gangs manage to avoid (and indeed promote the exact opposite of) the loss of domestic power that would follow if they were to bring about the same results more directly. Think of it as the geopolitical version of Strangers on a Train.

No, I’m not suggesting that Hezbollah and the Israeli government are in cahoots. They don’t need to be. This is how the logic of statism works, this is how its incentives play out, regardless of what its agents specifically intend. The externalisation of costs is what states do best. (True, Hezbollah isn’t a state, but it aspires to be one, and its actions are played out within a framework sustained by statism.)

What would happen if the civilian populations of Israel and Lebanon were to come to see this conflict, not as Israel versus Hezbollah, or even Israeli-government-plus-Israeli-civilians versus Hezbollah-plus-Lebanese-civilians, but rather as Israeli-government-plus-Hezbollah versus ordinary-people-living-on-the-eastern-Mediterranean? Both Hezbollah and the Israeli government would quickly lose their popular support, and their ability to wage war against each other would go with it.

But by encouraging the identification of civilians with the states that rule them, statism makes it harder for civilians to find their way to such a perspective. (Of course racism and religious intolerance are part of the story too – yet another way in which such cultural values help to prop up the state apparatus.) As long as the people of the eastern Mediterranean continue to view this conflict through statist spectacles, Hezbollah and/or the Israeli government will continue to be the victors, while the civilian populace in both Israel and Lebanon will remain the vanquished and victimised.

Posted July 21st, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#11
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Stop Me Before I Link Again!

What? Another post of nothing but links?

Yeah. You got a problem with that?


Posted July 18th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#10
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Who Is My Neighbour?

Is this an Israeli boy wounded by Hezbollah missiles in Haifa?

Or is it a Lebanese boy wounded by Israeli missiles in Beirut?


Does it matter? Do his right to life, and his claim on our compassion, depend on which answer is correct?

In 1851, Herbert Spencer wrote:

Morality knows nothing of geographical boundaries, or distinctions of race. You may put men on opposite sides of a river or a chain of mountains; may else part them by a tract of salt water; may give them, if you like, distinct languages; and may even colour their skins differently; but you cannot change their fundamental relationships. Originating as these do in the facts of man’s constitution, they are unalterable by the accidents of external condition. The moral law is cosmopolite – is no respecter of nationalities: and between men who are the antipodes of each other, either in locality or anything else, there must still exist the same balance of rights as though they were next-door neighbours in all things.
This insight instantly disposes of the sophistries of those who claim that a person’s rights to travel freely, to contact a lawyer, or not to be tortured, depend on his or her possession of American citizenship.

It also casts a stern judgment on the practice of dividing the victims of collateral damage into “worthy” and “unworthy” – into those who do, and those who do not, deserve expressions of outrage on their behalf, depending on which side of some blood-soaked political boundary they fall.

Posted July 17th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#09
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Forgotten Blues

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

The Alabama Philosophical Society (for which I’m the webmaster, archivist, and secretary-treasurer) will be holding its Annual Meeting on October 20-21, 2006, at the University of Alabama in Tuscaloosa. Derk Pereboom will be our Keynote Speaker.

Check out the website for paper submissions, student essay contest, hotel info, and other details.

If the title of this blog post puzzles you, click here.

Posted July 16th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#08
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Bastille Day Bulletin, Part Deux

A couple of follow-ups to yesterday’s post:


Posted July 15th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#07
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Bastille Day Bulletin

More miscellaneous musings:


Posted July 14th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#06
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Soccer Logic, Time Thieves, and Anarchy

Some miscellaneous musings:


Posted July 13th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#05
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Subversive Summer Reading

Still too busy to do much more than toss some more links your way:

Oh, by the way, you can now compare the new LP platform with the previous one. The changes aren’t quite as disastrous as some early reports indicated, but it’s still a long step down in my book.

Posted July 12th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#04
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Two From Space

Just now came across this great parable Space Aliens from Luxembourg by Stefan Molyneux, on the Iraq invasion.

NASA’s ongoing inability to solve the space shuttle’s foam problems brings to mind another great space parable, the anonymously authored How the West Wasn’t Won.

Posted July 11th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#03
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Betrayal in Portland

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

Meeting in Portland over (ironically enough) Independence Day weekend, the Libertarian Party convention ended up gutting the LP Platform, removing nearly all of the more radical planks (including the antiwar one). The new watered-down platform hasn’t been made available online yet, but preliminary details, and some reactions, are available here, here, here, and here.

The outfit behind this move calls itself the Libertarian Reform Caucus. Their theory is a simple one: most voters are not libertarians, so if the Libertarian Party wants to win elections, it must stop being libertarian.

That’s not quite how the Caucus words it, of course. Instead they accuse the Platform of “sacrificing practicality and political appeal in favor of philosophical consistency”; and they call instead for a Platform that sets out “a realistic vision for the next few years, as opposed to an idealistic vision of a libertarian future.”

To this sort of thing I can make no better reply than Hayek’s in his 1949 essay The Intellectuals and Socialism:

We must make the building of a free society once more an intellectual adventure, a deed of courage. What we lack is a liberal Utopia, a program which seems neither a mere defense of things as they are nor a diluted kind of socialism, but a truly liberal radicalism ... which is not too severely practical, and which does not confine itself to what appears today as politically possible. We need intellectual leaders who are willing to work for an ideal, however small may be the prospects of its early realization. They must be men who are willing to stick to principles and to fight for their full realization, however remote. ... Free trade and freedom of opportunity are ideals which still may arouse the imaginations of large numbers, but a mere “reasonable freedom of trade” or a mere “relaxation of controls” is neither intellectually respectable nor likely to inspire any enthusiasm. The main lesson which the true liberal must learn from the success of the socialists is that it was their courage to be Utopian which gained them the support of the intellectuals and therefore an influence on public opinion which is daily making possible what only recently seemed utterly remote. Those who have concerned themselves exclusively with what seemed practicable in the existing state of opinion have constantly found that even this had rapidly become politically impossible as the result of changes in a public opinion which they have done nothing to guide. Unless we can make the philosophic foundations of a free society once more a living intellectual issue, and its implementation a task which challenges the ingenuity and imagination of our liveliest minds, the prospects of freedom are indeed dark. But if we can regain that belief in the power of ideas which was the mark of liberalism at its best, the battle is not lost.
Or in Garrison’s words: “Gradualism in theory is perpetuity in practice.” (See also Rothbard here and Anthony Gregory here.)

Well, does it matter? If I regarded having a libertarian political party as the essential core of libertarian strategy, I would regard the Portland debacle as a major disaster. If instead I agreed with the Konkinites and Voluntaryists that political parties have no place in libertarian strategy, I would shrug my shoulders and say “what do you expect? good riddance.” But (for reasons I explain toward the end of my recent anarchism lecture) I’m actually somewhere in between: I think libertarian strategy should focus primarily on education and building alternative institutions, but I think a political party has a significant albeit secondary role to play in the process. (I guess that makes me a “Moderate Agorist” – a rara avis indeed?) So from my point of view, the reformist takeover of the LP Convention, while it isn’t the end of the world, is still an evil worth fighting.

The success of the reformists isn’t inevitable. They did a lot of hard work to push their victory through. We who prefer a consistent defense of liberty need to do a lot of hard work to roll that victory back.

The strategic question is, should reformism be fought from within the Party – or from without, by starting a new and more consistent party? At this point it’s probably too soon to say. Accordingly, I favour exploring both strategies in parallel. Specifically, I currently support and recommend both the Grassroots Libertarian Caucus and the Boston Tea Party. (About the latter see here.)

As always, Fight the Power.

Posted July 7th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#02
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


A Thought for the Fourth

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

(I’m going to be away from my computer on the Fourth, so I’m posting my Independence Day observations a day early.)

How should we think about the American Revolution? I suggest we should think of it as an uncompleted project. The Revolution, after all, wasn’t just about separation from Britain; it was about the right of the people to “alter or abolish” any political arrangements destructive of the “inalienable rights” of “life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness” or not resting on the “consent of the governed.”

Those were the principles on which the Revolution was based. But the political system the founders established never fully embodied those principles in practice; and its present-day successor no longer respects them even in theory. (Slogans, need I add? are not theory.)

Over the years since 1776, the fortunes of American liberty, and indeed of liberty worldwide, have risen and fallen; most often some aspects have risen while others have fallen. But every increase in liberty has involved the logical carrying-out of the principles of ’76, while every decrease has involved their de facto repudiation. (And if the average American is on balance more free than his or her 18th-century counterpart, this is small reason for complacency when one views the matter counterfactually. To paraphrase my comments in an L&P discussion last year: “For me the point of comparison is not USA 2006 vs. USA 1776, but USA 2006 vs. the USA 2006 we would have had if the USA had stuck consistently to those principles.)

From an establishment perspective, the Fourth of July is a day to celebrate the existing American system. But that approach to the Fourth is, I suggest, profoundly counter-revolutionary. Far better to regard Independence Day as a day to rededicate ourselves to forwarding the ongoing Revolution whose true completion, as Voltairine de Cleyre and Rose Wilder Lane argued here and here, will be libertarian anarchy.



In other news, recordings of my Mises seminar are now all online.

Also, don’t miss two excellent recent posts about the relation between poverty and statism by Sheldon Richman and Ben Kilpatrick.

Have a surly and rebellious Fourth!!

Posted July 3rd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog07-06.htm#01
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Aristotle, Anarchy, Action!

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

I’m back from San Diego, but once again I’m too busy to blog about it. (My backlog of things I want to blog about – my b(ack!)log? – has grown to monstrous dimensions.) But I’m not too busy to engage in a bit of shameless self-promotion:

Tomorrow I start my philosophy seminar on the praxeological foundations of libertarian ethics. To quote the prospectus:

On the one hand, the subjective-value approach to economics characteristic of the Austrian school might seem inhospitable to objective theories of ethical value. Yet on the other hand, philosophers like Socrates, Aristotle, and Aquinas based their objective conceptions of ethics on something rather like a praxeological analysis of subjective valuation; indeed, subjectivist economics and natural law ethics both originated from this common tradition. Can an objective ethics in a broadly Aristotelean tradition be grounded in praxeological considerations? And if so, what shape might a radical libertarian political theory take if built on such foundations?

The first half of the seminar will deal with the praxeological foundations of ethics. Topics include: do human beings have an ultimate end? can we knowingly choose the bad? how are morality and self-interest related? why should we care about other people’s interests? ...

The second half of the seminar will explore the implications of praxeological, Aristotelean ethics for such issues as property rights, contracts, land ownership, punishment and restitution, military policy, stateless legal systems, utilitarian vs. rights-based considerations, and the cultural preconditions of liberty.
A live webcast of the seminar will be available here, presumably followed eventually by archived recordings here.

There will also be two bonus lectures by David Gordon, on Narveson and Nozick. Be there or B2!

Posted June 25th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog06-06.htm#03
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


 Alcazar Gardens, El Prado, Balboa Park, San Diego

Before the Law Stands a Doorkeeper

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

The more “moderate” opponents of immigration are often heard saying, “fine, let people immigrate by all means, but they should do it the legal way.”

A fair response to this bromide would be: “What legal way?” As this article shows, for most low-skilled Mexican workers there is no legal way to enter the United States. The U.S. has a quota of 5,000 green cards for low-skilled workers; that’s just one percent of the number seeking to come in. For the rest, the alternative is a temporary work permit, but getting one of those “often requires the worker to ... pay off someone in Mexico.”

In short, there are Mexicans who want to work, and there are Americans who want to employ them, but the U.S. and (despite popular impressions) the Mexican governments have conspired to prevent, at gunpoint, these peaceful and mutually beneficial transactions.

In other news, I’m off to a joint Liberty Fund / Social Philosophy and Policy Center conference (topic: ancient political thought) in San Diego / La Jolla; back next week. I lived in San Diego in the early 70s, but haven’t seen it since 1977; it’ll be nice to see it again.

Posted June 13th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog06-06.htm#02
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Stromberg on Land Theft: Now Online

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

I’m back from Scotland! But more about that later.

Joseph Stromberg’s excellent 1995 article “English Enclosures and Soviet Collectivization: Two Instances of an Anti-Peasant Mode of Development,” which appeared in the first (and alas only) issue of Sam Konkin’s journal The Agorist Quarterly, has been getting some attention in the left-libertarian blogosphere lately (see, e.g., here and here). Stromberg explores the illuminating parallels between what are often thought of as very disparate events (since one is supposed to be a black mark for “capitalism” and the other for “socialism,” whatever exactly those terms mean).

I thought the article deserved a wider audience, particularly in light of the ongoing debate among libertarians concerning land reform and the “subsidy of history.” So with Stromberg’s kind permission, I’ve placed it online on the Molinari Institute site. Check it out here.

The other articles in that issue are worth reading also, so I’m going to try to get permission from the various authors to post the whole issue. Thus far I’ve gotten approval from E. Scott Royce and Jared C. Lobdell (for their articles “The Black Market Response to Rationing During World War II” and “Old Rightists and Old Writers,” respectively); waiting to hear from the others. Watch this space ....

Posted June 8th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog06-06.htm#01
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


 Is this the dreaded Bran Mak Morn?

Forth to the Firth!

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

I’ve been planning for ages to write about my Vegas and Prague trips/conferences, as well as to add some further thoughts on the French rioters (remember them?). I’ve even got a catchy title for the post: APEE, PCPE, and CPE.

Well, I’ve been way too busy to get to it, and on Thursday I leave for Edinburgh (ah, Scotland! land of Adam Smith, David Hume, Thomas Reid, Duns Scotus, and most importantly Bran Mak Morn!) so it’ll have to wait a little bit longer. Back in a week!

Posted May 23rd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog05-06.htm#06
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Subjective Value, Objective Good

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

A text version of my August 2005 talk “Economics and Its Ethical Assumptions” is now online. (Thanks to B. K. Marcus for editing it to make it a bit less transcript-y.)

In it I talk about the relation between subjectivism about economic value and objectivism about ethical value, and do my usual song-and-dance about fusing the Austrian and Athenian traditions.

The talk also serves as a useful preview of the sort of thing I’ll be talking about in my upcoming week-long Mises Institute seminar.

Posted May 19th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog05-06.htm#05
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


 Jean-Baptiste Say

Oh Say Can You See

I’ve previously described how to find the graves of Gustave de Molinari and Benjamin Constant in Paris’s Père Lachaise cemetery; see the map below on the left. I noted at that time that although I knew the grave of another great libertarian thinker, Jean-Baptiste Say, was nearby, I was unable to locate it on my last trip to Paris.

Now, between advice from Hervé de Quengo and coming across a more complete map, I can describe the location of Say’s grave more precisely. On the map below on the right, the lower green rectangle marks Constant’s grave; the upper green rectangle marks Say’s.

   


Also, de Quengo writes:

Well, go to the Constant/Molinari tombs. You then have to continue along the Chemin Masséna towards Chemin Suchet. You will find en passant the French tomb of the Maréchal Ney .... You will find yourself at a crossroads: Chemin Suchet, Chemin Jordan and Chemin Masséna.

Take the Chemin Masséna [judging from the map I think he means Chemin Suchet – RTL] and look at your left. You will first find the tomb of the Prince Murat. At 25 paces from the crossroads, you will see the huge Sépulture de Mme. D’Aumont, Duchesse de Mazarin. J.-B. Say is just behind: currently, you can see his name from the road.
I hope to find it next time I’m in Paris.

Posted May 19th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog05-06.htm#04
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Name the Mystery Feminist

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

Who wrote the following passages?

1. If he loves you in the right way he’ll not stop you. You were just made for the stage, Anne, and if anyone interferes with your career now you’d never forgive him in after years – you’d always be thinking of what you might have achieved. ... Suppose you didn’t like the motion picture business and made him give up his theaters? He’d always brood about that and be unhappy. You’ll be unhappy if you can’t go ahead with your work, that you love. In either event an unhappy home will result, but if he keeps his beloved picture houses and you stay on the stage you’re both happy in your work, and that’s a longer stride toward mutual happiness than starting out on your married life with one of you harboring a regret that may easily grow into a chronic condition of discontent and unhappiness.

2. That is a question that should never arise between two people unselfishly in love with one another. The man would never make it necessary for her to choose – he would encourage her. ... After all, happiness is all that counts in life. There isn’t so much of it running around loose in the world that a man can afford to deny his wife the right to win it in any clean and decent way that she sees fit.

3. If you mean [I should stay] in the kitchen, then I can tell you that [no] woman with a nervous organization higher than a cow’s, is ever satisfied with that. Lots of us have to do it, but that does not mean that we like it and I’ll be darned if I’m going to peel potatoes and swat flies all the rest of my life when I have the brains and the chance to do something else .... I want to think for myself and use the brains the Lord gave me ... I want to rise above the mediocrity of a household drudge ....

4. You say that you love us. You say that you want homes and wives. All you love is your own selfish comforts and desires. ... Your idea of home is a breeding plant. ... Your ideas of marital happiness start and end with yourselves – and having babies. If you have what you want – everything your own way – why, then, marriage is a blessing. You want us to sit at home without an interest in the world that we can call our very own – and raise children. ... I intend to have children; but I do not intend to devote my body and soul and mind exclusively to the business of breeding.
Read the answer.

Posted May 19th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog05-06.htm#03
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


The Net of Time

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

In the latest (June ’06) issue of Liberty, in a review of Stephen Cox’s excellent Isabel Paterson biography, Bruce Ramsey writes:

Though Paterson penned novels, some of which Cox says are good, all have been out of print for more than half a century.
I’ve read all eight of her published novels, and greatly enjoyed them. My copy of The Singing Season is autographed by Paterson herself:

To John Farrar
           With the sincere regards
           of a contributor to an
           editor and the indescribable
           sentiments of an author toward
          a possible critic
From Isabel Paterson
But it’s not quite true to say that her novels are all long out of print. As I’ve blogged previously, Paterson’s Never Ask the End was recently reissued by Kessinger Publishing. (Some of Kessinger’s reprints are shoddy disasters – see my Amazon review of their messed-up edition of Lysander Spooner’s Vices Are Not Crimes, for example – but this Paterson one is just fine.)

Is it any good? Judge for yourself. Here’s an in my opinion beautiful excerpt in which the protagonist is contemplating the statues in the garden of my beloved Musée Cluny in Paris. (The garden, while still lovely, nowadays no longer contains these statues, but you can see photos here of how they once looked.)

Sitting on the steps of the side entrance, with her chin on her hand, she discovered why she had stopped here. In the long grass of the garden, fragments of medieval sculpture reposed tranquilly. Their granite features were blunted, all but effaced. It gave them a ghostly aspect, an infinite calm. It is the material substance that is ghostly, she thought. It wears thin, dissolving with time. Something more powerful and enduring wears it out ... The soul, having stooped to embrace mortality, is caught in the net of time. It strives to break through by the keen devices of the intellect, by the intensity of passion, the persuasion of tenderness, even the violence of anger; and falls back on silence at the last. But at parting it cries out, wait, one moment more and I could have told you ... oh, wait! What we desire is communication. ... Perhaps, some other where, we achieve it, by a persistence to which even granite must yield.

Posted May 18th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog05-06.htm#02
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Francis Tandy Rides Again

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

Francis Tandy’s 1896 book Voluntary Socialism is one of the classics of market anarchism. (Don’t be misled by the title; Tandy, a disciple of Benjamin Tucker, uses the term “socialism” in the sense employed by “free-market socialists” like Tucker, Stephen Pearl Andrews, and, today, Kevin Carson.) A good many political philosophers have probably seen Tandy’s name at some point, since Robert Nozick cites him early on in Anarchy, State, and Utopia, in a list of proponents of competing protection agencies; the others listed are Spooner, Tucker, Rothbard, Friedman, and the Tannehills. (Nozick appears unaware of the battlin’ Belgians Molinari and de Puydt.) Nevertheless, Tandy is far and away the most obscure name on the list, and his book is damnably hard to find; and apparently the Denver Public Library (where Tandy, a Denver resident, once worked) possesses one of the few existing copies but refuses to allow it be photocopied.

Happily, I managed to get my hands on the elusive 1979 Revisionist Press reprint version a couple of years ago, and I’ve just now posted the first five chapters on the Molinari site. (I had already posted the preface and introduction back in March ’04.)

The first four of these chapters set out the psychological, sociological, and ethical foundations of Tandy’s libertarianism. This section is rather a mixed bag from my point of view; Tandy’s theory of human action combines praxeological insight with psychologistic confusion, and his blend of Stirner and Spencer manages at times to look more like stereotypical “Social Darwinism” than does either Stirner or Spencer singly. Still, there’s plenty of good stuff here.

But what the book is best known for (well, to the extent that it’s known at all!) is its fifth chapter, which is devoted to an explanation and defense of the concept of competing protection agencies – in its day, one of the fullest discussions of the idea post-Molinari. It’s fascinating to see how many of the standard moves in market anarchist theory today are already in evidence in Tandy.

More chapters to follow! In the meantime, enjoy.

Posted May 16th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog05-06.htm#01
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


One More Atlas Post

Here are Pitt and Jolie looking their most Randian:



Posted April 29th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog04-06.htm#07
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Who Is Brad Pitt?

Follow-up to yesterday’s post: On second look at the TOC report, I notice it says: “The film will be based on a script of the first part of the novel .... It is anticipated ‘Atlas’ will be a multi-part film.”

That’s good news too – it would be nice to see Atlas get the Lord of the Rings treatment. But it does raise a question about Pitt’s alleged casting as Galt in this first film. Galt doesn’t appear in person until the final third of the book; so if Pitt is in the first film, either he’s playing someone other than Galt (Rearden, perhaps?), or else, more likely, they’re changing the story. Oh well.

Posted April 29th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog04-06.htm#06
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Dagny Taggart, Tomb Raider; or, Tyler Durden Shrugged

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

The Atlas Shrugged film project, which has been languishing in development hell for, like, ever, seems to be making progress toward actuality once again, this time under the auspices of Lionsgate. Moreover, the Objectivist Center reports that Angelina Jolie and Brad Pitt are “interested in parts in the film.” Contact Music insists, less cautiously, that the movie will star Jolie and Pitt as Dagny Taggart and John Galt respectively.

I’m inclined to trust the more cautious over the less cautious report, but this casting would certainly be very good news. Not because Jolie and Pitt are ideal to play the roles – they’re not (though on the other hand I can certainly envision Hollywood making much worse choices) – but because their names attached to the picture would bring investor dollars now and viewers later. Keeping my fingers crossed ....

Posted April 28th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog04-06.htm#05
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Anarchy in Prague

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

Tomorrow I leave for the Prague Conference on Political Economy. This won’t be the farthest east I’ve gone in Europe, since Vietri sul Mare, on the west coast of Italy just south of Naples, is actually further east. (One of those things you don’t believe until you look at a map – like the fact that Reno, Nevada, is west of Los Angeles.) But it’ll be the farthest inland I’ve been in Europe, as well as my first visit to a former communist country.

The topic of my presentation is “Rule-following, Praxeology, and Anarchy.” Here’s an abstract:

The aim of Ludwig Wittgenstein’s “rule-following paradox” is to diagnose a seductive error that Wittgenstein sees as underlying a variety of different philosophical mistakes: the implicit assumption of the need for and/or possibility of a self-applying rule. A further implication of Wittgenstein’s diagnosis is that human action is not reducible either to purely mentalistic or to purely behavioural phenomena.

If, as I shall argue, Wittgenstein’s analysis is correct, then, I shall further argue, the rule-following paradox has important implications for two aspects of Austrian theory.

First, Wittgenstein’s argument sheds light on the relation between economic theory and economic history – i.e., between the aprioristic method of praxeology and the interpretive method of thymology, as Ludwig von Mises uses those terms in Theory and History. In particular, it shows that, just as thymological interpretation involves praxeological categories, so the possession of praxeological categories involves thymological experience – thus enabling a reconciliation of the superficially opposed insights of Mises’ Kantian approach, Murray Rothbard’s Aristotelean approach, and Don Lavoie’s hermeneutical approach to Austrian methodology.

Second, Wittgenstein’s argument provides a way of defending the stateless legal order advocated by Rothbard, Lavoie, and others. Critics of free-market anarchism often charge that a stateless society lacks, yet needs, a “final arbiter” or “ultimate authority” to resolve conflicts; but what such critics mean by a “final arbiter” turns out to be yet another version of the “self-applying rule” that Wittgenstein has shown is neither needed nor possible.
Adios till next week!

Posted April 18th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog04-06.htm#04
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


George Mason’s Feet of Clay

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

We should never let our admiration for a thinker’s virtues blind us to his flaws (or, of course, vice versa). Commenting on past U.S presidents, I recently wrote:

[I]t often seems like the better they are, the worse they are; i.e., when you look at the Presidents who did the most libertarian things, they always seem to be trying their damnedest to cancel out the merits of their pro-liberty achievements by turning around and doing the most horrifically anti-liberty things they can think of. (Jefferson, Jackson, and Lincoln all come to mind.)
Today’s Mises Daily Article by Norman Van Cott makes a similar point about another founding father with some libertarian credentials, George Mason. When he was good, he was very good; but when he was bad he really wallowed in despicable hypocrisy.

Mason pretended his opposition to the slave trade was based on grounds of justice and humanity, but the fact that he combined opposition to the importation of slaves with support for the strengthening of protections for domestic slaveowners suggests that his motivations were rather more along protectionist lines. As Van Cott writes, “the hypocrisy of the juxtaposed arguments is mind-boggling.” Read the article.

Posted April 17th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog04-06.htm#03
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


The Red Flag of Rothbard

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

My Rothbard Memorial Lecture is now available in text, audio, and video formats. In it I try to delineate Rothbard’s legacy for the libertarian left, including a discussion of the relation between free-market anarchism and participatory democracy.

I should add a thank you to Wally Conger, Brad Spangler, and Sheldon Richman for their very generous comments (which I am too vain not to link to).

Posted April 7th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog04-06.htm#02
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


JLS 20.1: What Lies Within?
Mutualist Admiration Society, or Mutualist Assured Destruction?


[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

I’m back from Vegas, but a bit under the weather; I’ll blog about the conference and other matters later. But while I was away, the latest issue (20.1) of the Journal of Libertarian Studies came out, and as is my wont I’m writing a brief plug.

 A snapshot of Kevin Carson after too long a day at the beach Kevin Carson (check out his website and blog) is one of the most interesting thinkers on the contemporary libertarian left, and his book Studies in Mutualist Political Economy is a fascinating read. While I’m not convinced by two of Carson’s major theses – the impermissibility of absentee landownership and the superiority of (a subjectivised version of) the labour theory of value – his case for them is subtle and sophisticated, and deserves grappling with. Moreover, the book is filled with extremely valuable material – including a trenchant analysis of what Carson calls “vulgar libertarianism,” meaning the error of sliding from a defense of genuine free markets to a defense of present-day neomercantilist corporatism – that one can largely appreciate whether or not one buys into the two aforementioned theses.

Anyway, I figure Carson’s claims deserve a hearing to whatever extent they are right, and deserve a rebuttal to whatever extent they are wrong; accordingly, this symposium issue of the JLS is devoted to examining Carson’s work from an Austrian perspective (or, as it turns out, several Austrian perspectives); it includes critiques by Bob Murphy, Walter Block, George Reisman, and myself, and a reply by Carson. You can read my summary of the contents here; and the articles themselves are already online here.

For some of the discussion this issue is already generating, see here, here, here, here, here, here, and here.

Read summaries of previous issues under my editorship here.

Read back issues online here.

Subscribe here.

Posted April 6th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog04-06.htm#01
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Happiness in Las Vegas

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

Tomorrow I’m off to Las Vegas for the (unluckily monikered) APEE, where I’ll be contributing to a panel on “Happiness: Philosophical and Economic Perspectives.” (Essentially I’ll be trying to defend an Aristotelean conception of happiness on praxeological grounds.) Take a look at the participant list and you’ll see why it would be a bad thing for the libertarian movement if Vegas got nuked over the weekend.

I have more to say about the French situation, but it’ll have to wait until I get back.

In the meantime, check out Charles’ recent rebuttal of a frequent argument against worker-run industry, as well as an interesting discussion of urban vs. agrarian virtues in the comments section of his recent post on immigration.

Posted March 31st, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#13
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Subversion from the Sea

I’m continuing to work my way through some of the lesser-known works of Jules Verne and H. G. Wells, and thought I would comment on the two latest:


Posted March 26th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#12
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Another Loony Left-Libertarian Screed from Roderick

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

What the current protests in France are about, at least inter alia, is the French government’s proposal to allow employers to fire their workers – a right they’re currently not allowed.

 Agora! Anarchy! Action! It might seem clear which side a libertarian has to be on in this dispute: of course libertarians favour freedom of association, which includes the freedom of either party to exit an employment contract. Thus the new proposal apparently represents a move in the direction of a free market: the government is right, and the protestors are wrong.

But things aren’t quite so simple.

Of course in a free market there would be no legal restrictions (except those contractually agreed to) on an employer’s right to fire an employee. But from the fact that there would be no X in a free society, it doesn’t follow that absolutely any situation will be moved in the direction of freedom simply by removing X. (Compare: from the fact that a healthy person wouldn’t have a pacemaker, it doesn’t follow that the health of anyone who has a pacemaker would be improved by its removal.)

As I recently wrote elsewhere:

Whether something counts as a reduction of restrictions on liberty depends on the context. Remember when Reagan “deregulated” the Savings & Loans – such deregulation could be a good thing under many circumstances, but given that he didn’t remove federal deposit insurance, “deregulation” amounted in that context to an increase of aggression against the taxpayers, licensing the S&Ls to takes greater risks with taxpayers’ money.

So in this case: when government passes laws giving group A unjust privileges over group B, and then passes another law giving B some protection against A, then repealing the second law without repealing the first amounts to increasing A’s unjust privilege over B. Of course a free society would have neither the first nor the second law, but repealing them in the wrong order can actually decrease rather than increase liberty.
Just as deregulating the S&Ls doesn’t count as a move toward liberty if it isn’t accompanied by an end to tax-funded deposit insurance, so in general a removal of restrictions on an entity doesn’t count as a move toward liberty if the entity is still a substantial recipient of government privilege or subsidy. For the more that an entity benefits from government intervention, the closer it comes to being an arm of the State – in which case lifting restrictions on it is, to that extent, lifting restrictions on the State.

As Kevin Carson writes:

[S]ince the state’s intervention, directly or indirectly, has been in the interests of the plutocracy, it matters a great deal which functions of the state should be axed first. The first to go should be those forms of intervention in the market that subsidize economic centralization and the concentration of wealth, reduce the bargaining power of labor, and ensure monopoly returns to the owners of land and capital. The last to go should be those government functions that make the system of class exploitation marginally bearable for labor. In the words of Thomas Knapp of the Democratic Freedom Caucus, that means cutting welfare from the top down, and taxes from the bottom up.
While I don’t agree with Kevin as to what in every case counts as “monopoly returns to the owners of land and capital” (he thinks absentee land ownership is unjust, I don’t – see our exchange on Lockean vs. Tuckerite theories of property rights in the forthcoming issue of JLS), I certainly agree with the general sentiment.

To clarify: the claim is not that we need to favour some restrictions on liberty now in order to gain greater liberty later. There are plenty who’ve held that view, from Marx to Chomsky to Victor Yarros – but not me, comrade. The claim is rather that what would count as lifting a restriction on liberty in one context does not so count in another context.

All this is by way of introduction to fellow left-libertarian blogospheroid Brad Spangler’s letter to the French protestors, which expresses solidarity with their struggle while disambiguating genuine from faux market reform and inviting the protestors to adopt libertarian aims and methods. Of course I had to sign it, since it begins with a quotation from me! (By coincidence, the Rothbard Memorial Lecture I delivered at the ASC last weekend ended with a quote from Brad. The mutualist admiration society continues .... And speaking whichly, congratulations to Wally Conger, another fellow left-libertarian blogospheroid, for being awarded the Karl Hess Club’s 2006 Samuel Edward Konkin III Memorial Chauntecleer. But wasn’t that the name of a play by Ayn Rand’s favourite playwright?)

1968: back by popular demand!

Posted March 25th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#11
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


How Victor Yarros Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the State

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

There is no danger of my finding Anarchism ridiculous and abandoning it.
– Victor S. Yarros, Liberty, 13 August 1887

Victor Yarros, who now parades in the role of a mere observer, was for years
my most active participant in Anarchistic propaganda, – a fact which he is
now at pains to conceal. I once admired him; I now despise him.

– Benjamin R. Tucker, Free Vistas 2 (1937)


Victor Yarros – our mystery philosopher from a few weeks back – was one of the leading figures of 19th-century American anarchism: disciple of Herbert Spencer, populariser of Lysander Spooner, and sometime co-editor of Benjamin Tucker’s periodical Liberty.

In the 20th century, however, Yarros eventually repudiated anarchism in favour of social democracy – becoming an admirer of the policies of Wilson and FDR, waxing enthusiastic about the T.V.A., and apparently even making his peace with the Soviet Union, though he remained skeptical of Marxism. (He also became an adherent to logical positivism, though oddly still combining this with a kind of ethical naturalism à la Spencer. He had already long since repudiated his brief flirtation with Tucker’s Stirnerite egoism in favour of a more Spencerian natural-rights position; for my own take on the Stirnerians-versus-Spencerians controversy, see my blog post Egoism and Anarchy.)

 Victor Yarros I’ve just posted, on the Molinari site, three articles in which Yarros discusses individualist anarchism and explains the origins of his increasing dissatisfaction with it. In Benjamin R. Tucker and Philosophical Anarchism, Yarros gives a somewhat sympathetic account of the position he no longer holds, but in Adventures in the Realm of Ideas he is rather more hostile to Tucker’s ideas, and in The Persistence of Utopian Thinking he extends the same critique inter alia to Albert J. Nock.

Yarros accuses his former anarchist colleagues of “utopianism,” by which he means any attempt to “plan societies and civilizations in complete ignorance of, and indifference to, the human materials and instruments involved.” Yarros’s description is reminiscent of Adam Smith’s portrait of the “man of system,” who “seems to imagine that he can arrange the different members of a great society with as much ease as the hand arranges the different pieces upon a chess-board,” neglecting to consider that while “the pieces upon the chess-board have no other principle of motion besides that which the hand impresses upon them,” yet “in the great chess-board of human society, every single piece has a principle of motion of its own, altogether different from that which the legislature might choose to impress upon it.”

Now this might seem an odd indictment to make of the anarchist, who proposes to leave people alone rather than impose any legislative blueprint on them. But Yarros believes that those who agitate for the abolition of the State have “no conception of human nature as it is.”

Now Yarros is certainly right in condemning attempts to realise a political program without taking into account “[t]ime, place, conditions, [and] realities.” (Chris Sciabarra has likewise offered an excellent critique of this sort of utopianism in his book Total Freedom, where he too suggests that the critique may apply to anarchism – though I should add that Chris’s distance from anarchism, if distance it be, is far shorter than that of Yarros in these essays. My review of Chris’s book will be online eventually, i.e., as soon as I get around to it; in the meantime, see the summary and Chris’s reply.) But are anarchists really guilty of the error in question? Yarros writes:

Of all the possible and impossible Utopias, that of the Philosophical Anarchists is, of course, the most preposterous one. How many persons of the world today can even imagine a society without the State? The first thing people do under pioneering conditions is to organize a government. The first thing people in distress do at any time is to appeal to the State for aid.
Now if all that Yarros means is that most people nowadays are not anarchists, and that converting them to anarchism will likely be a long and difficult process, that’s not news to the anarchists; and merely embracing a long-term program can’t be sufficient to earn one the title of utopian. Nor, despite occasional gestures in this direction, can Yarros really mean that anarchism’s focus on a long-term ideal prevents them from supporting any short-term reformist measures; for he himself notes that the Tuckerites “knew very well that progress toward their goal would be slow,” and “rejoiced in small steps toward their goal” so long as none of these intermediate measures “in any degree extended the sphere of government or compulsion.” And if Yarros means that getting people to accept a stateless social order is not just a long-term but an impossible goal, we may simply point to the evidence collected by libertarian historians (see, e.g., Tom Bell’s bibliographical essay) to demonstrate that such stateless orders have in fact developed frequently through history, including “under pioneering conditions.”

In any case, one fundamental reason for rejecting the charge of utopianism is that the institutions and incentives to which anarchists look as the basis for social order in a stateless future are not imaginary constructions which might or might not work in practice; they are already here and already functioning. Thomas Paine made the point in The Rights of Man:

Great part of that order which reigns among mankind is not the effect of government. It has its origin in the principles of society and the natural constitution of man. It existed prior to government, and would exist if the formality of government was abolished. The mutual dependence and reciprocal interest which man has upon man, and all the parts of civilised community upon each other, create that great chain of connection which holds it together. ... In fine, society performs for itself almost everything which is ascribed to government.
Or, as Rothbard observed in “The Spooner-Tucker Doctrine: An Economist’s View” (which is scheduled be reprinted in the next issue of JLS), the market anarchists of the 19th century not only “advanced libertarian individualism from a protest against existing evils to pointing the way to an ideal society toward which we can move,” but “correctly located that ideal in the free market which already partially existed and was providing vast economic and social benefits”; in this respect, Rothbard argues, the anarchists “greatly surpassed previous ‘utopians’ in locating [their] goal in already-existing institutions rather than in a coercive or impossible vision of a transformed mankind.”

 Benjamin Tucker Yarros’s real objection to anarchism, it transpires, is not that it rejects all intermediate measures simpliciter, but rather that it rejects all intermediate measures that increase State power. By opposing the growth of the State, Yarros charges, the anarchists have “played into the hands of the Bourbons and Tories” and given “aid and comfort to plutocracy,” since “the defenders of plutocracy and monopoly have talked and written exactly as the Anarchists have.”

Well, it is certainly true that plutocratic conservatives have often invoked the same sort of anti-government rhetoric that free-market anarchists use. But the conservative employment of such rhetoric is manifestly insincere – as Yarros is well aware. For as he goes on to explain, the corporate elite’s opposition to government intervention is selective; they “hate government when it makes too many concessions to labor or to progressivism, or undertakes to curb greed and tyranny on the part of capital and finance,” but to “special privilege, of which capital and Big Business are the beneficiaries, there is never any objection from that quarter.” There’s nothing new about bad guys aping the rhetoric of good guys; their doing so is no argument against the good guys. There must be more to Yarros’s objection than this.

And indeed there is; for along with his increased pessimism about anarchy went increased optimism about the state. In particular, Yarros had come to reject the view that the state is necessarily a tool of the ruling class:

The American farmers do not regard the State as their enemy. They are grateful to it for small favors; and organized labor is equally grateful for like favors. If the State is the enemy, what is Plutocracy, and what is predatory big business? ...

[W]hatever the origin of the State, it was absurd to assert that it was always and inevitably the instrument of privilege and monopoly, and must remain such under all conditions. The evidence glaringly contradicted that conception. The democratic governments have increasingly yielded to the pressure of farmers, wage workers, and middle-class reformers.

The hatred of our plutocrats and reactionaries for the New Deal is alone sufficient to dispose of the charge that the State is simply the tool of the economic oligarchy. In the past, the same interests bitterly fought Woodrow Wilson�s reform program, and fought in vain.
Yarros concludes that state power is now a viable tool in the struggle against plutocracy: “Where democracy is strong and mature, the State serves the interests of the masses, not of the classes.” Here, once again, Yarros’s theories run up against historical facts. As libertarian and New Left historians have exhaustively demonstrated (see, for example, Gabriel Kolko’s The Triumph of Conservatism: A Reinterpretation of American History, 1900-1916, Butler Shaffer’s In Restraint of Trade: The Business Campaign Against Competition, 1918-1938, and other sources cited here), big business interests were the chief beneficiaries of Wilson’s and Roosevelt’s economic programs, whose cartelising measures functioned to insulate the corporate elite from upstart competition. By supporting such measures, it was Yarros, not Tucker or Nock, who was playing into the hands of the plutocracy.

Does this mean that the business lobby’s hostility to the New Deal was pure fakery? No, not entirely; but Yarros misunderstands its significance. As I wrote in my Rothbard Memorial Lecture:

We might compare the alliance between government and big business to the alliance between church and state in the Middle Ages. Of course it’s in the interest of both parties to maintain the alliance – but all the same, each side would like to be the dominant partner, so it’s no surprise that the history of such alliances will often look like a history of conflict and antipathy, as each side struggles to get the upper hand. But this struggle must be read against a common background framework of cooperation to maintain the system of control.
Yarros allowed himself to be taken in by the populist veneer of the New Deal, but in fact the struggle between FDR and the business lobby was merely (with a few honourable exceptions) a squabble between two different flavours of fascism – with each faction far preferring the victory of its rival to any genuine liberalisation. And as for the gratitude of “organized labor” for governmental “favors,” the true legacy of New Deal labour legislation was to defang the labour movement by co-opting it into the corporate establishment.

According to Yarros, the “paternalistic and bureaucratic” character of statist collectivism, and its regrettable focus on “economic improvement” to the detriment of spiritual progress, are necessary byproducts of a temporary ’phase“ through which the struggle against plutocracy must pass; accordingly he counsels “opportunism,” “pragmatism,” and “cheerful acceptance of the unavoidable.” It’s not clear whether he’s talking about the Soviet Union or the New Deal; but “paternalistic” seems an odd term for Stalin’s reign of terror and democide, while Roosevelt’s corporatist policies – as Rothbard, Higgs, and others have shown – worsened economic misery rather than remedying it.

The individualist anarchists may not have been Austrians, but they certainly understood economics well enough to understand why the New Deal would be economically disastrous; Yarros seems to have forgotten much that he had once known. As for the Soviet Union, Yarros traveled there several times – but unlike Emma Goldman, Alexander Berkman, Rose Wilder Lane, and Bertrand Russell, he does not seem to have profited from the experience.

Yarros’s work – even his later, post-anarchist work! – contains much that is interesting and valuable, and I will probably post more congenial fare from him in the future. But against anarchism Yarros’s charge of utopianism misfires; in seeking to obtain libertarian goals by increasing the power of the centralised coercive state, Yarros proved himself to be the true utopian.

Posted March 25th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#10
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


This Is a Stick-Up

So, here’s a bumper sticker I’d like to see:


Posted March 23rd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#09
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


This Week in Review

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

A rundown of my adventures for this past week or so:


Posted March 20th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#08
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Traduttore Traditore

To a reader just starting Jules Verne’s 1877 novel Hector Servadac, it wouldn’t be obvious that this was to be one of Verne’s science fiction novels. On the contrary, the opening chapters – featuring a French military officer in North Africa, preparing to fight a duel with a romantic rival – might lead the reader to expect a straight, non-science-fictional adventure story (of which Verne wrote many).

It is not until the fourth chapter that it becomes evident that some sort of astronomical catastrophe has struck: suddenly gravity and air pressure are lower, the celestial bodies are all askew, etc. The characters begin to speculate that perhaps the Earth has been knocked off its axis; but it does not initially occur to them that they are no longer on the Earth. When eventually this thought does occur, the characters assume that they are at least on some large chunk of the Earth that has somehow gotten dislodged. It is not until the 26th chapter, over halfway through the book, that the characters discover that they are actually traveling on a comet which has barely grazed the Earth, carrying off some soil and water and a few unwilling passengers.

Presumably this is supposed to come as a surprise to the reader too. Maybe not quite as much of a surprise; Verne has been dropping clues all along, so the reader has a fair chance of figuring things out before the characters do. But even so, Verne plainly intends the reader to have to figure it out, rather than simply being told up front.

After all, many of Verne’s novels announce in their very titles what sort of adventure the reader is in for: Around the World in Eighty Days, 20,000 Leagues Under the Sea, Journey to the Centre of the Earth, From the Earth to the Moon, and so on. The fact that Verne by contrast gave this novel the non-committal title Hector Servadac suggests that he wanted to maintain some suspense as to what is really going on.

So what title did Verne’s English translators give to Hector Servadac? Why, Off On a Comet, of course! Thanks a lot, guys.

Posted March 12th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#07
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


A Late Delivery from Babylon

The last of the unreleased Babylon 5 shows is now finally being released on dvd, as a feature-length film titled Legend of the Rangers. This was originally To Live and Die in Starlight, the pilot for an unrealised Babylon 5 spinoff series to be titled Legend of the Rangers.

This disc now joins the original Babylon 5 pilot, seasons 1, 2, 3, 4, and 5, the tv-movies, and the other spinoff series Crusade.

I can’t say that this is Babylon 5 at its best; indeed I have the same gripe about Legend that I had about Thirdspace, namely that each of them introduces a new long-lost alien race that is supposed to be “even more terrifying than the Shadows.” The original series spent many, many episodes gradually building up the menace of the Shadows; there’s no way some Cthulhu-come-latelies can just waltz in after a few minutes’ exposition and expect to earn the same kind of audience reaction.

But it’s still a fun ride; and it features what now, sadly, turns out to be G’kar’s final appearance.

Posted March 10th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#06
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Wooly Bully; or, Mammoths Live!

They say that mammoths are extinct – but are they? Take a good look at this aerial photo:


These two entities are definitely mammoth-like in appearance (notice the long, curving tusks, much larger than elephant tusks). The one on the left seems to be trapped in an area of liquid, perhaps some kind of a tarpit; the one on the right stands on the shore near the tree, helpless to assist its conspecific.

This is a real satellite photo; it has not been retouched in any way. Draw your own conclusions.

Posted March 10th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#05
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


 Leonard Cohen never drinks ... wine

I’ve Been Memed!*** – Part Deux

I notice that some versions of the “Meme*** of Fours” include the category �Four albums I can’t live without.� So here are mine:

1. Leonard Cohen – The Essential Leonard Cohen
2. Lucinda Williams – Essence
3. Yeni Türkü – Külhani Şarkılar
4. Antonio Vivaldi – The Four Seasons

*** This time the term “meme” is being used literally. That’s right: I really am nothing more than a passive transmission device for autonomous units of information. But wait. That means it’s really the meme, not me, that’s writing this – in which case the words “me” and “I” must refer to the meme and not the, um, meat vehicle – which in turn implies that I am the meme writing this! Whew, glad we got that settled.

Posted March 8th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#04
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


I’ve Been Memed!*

Wally Conger has tagged me with the dreaded “Meme* of Fours.” I hereby discharge it.

Four jobs I’ve had

1. House painter
2. Amusement park ride operator
3. Grocery bagger
4. Academic summer program director
Four movies I can watch over and over
1. His Girl Friday
2. Ninotchka
3. To Have and Have Not
4. The Third Man
Four places I’ve lived
1. Colorado Springs, Colorado
2. San Diego, California
3. Hanover, New Hampshire
4. Chapel Hill, North Carolina
Four TV shows I love
1. The Twilight Zone (the original)
2. Secret Agent / Danger Man
3. Babylon 5
4. Firefly
Four highly regarded and recommended TV shows I haven’t seen (much of)
1. Lost
2. Alias
3. 24
4. Deadwood
Four places I’ve vacationed
1. London, England
2. Paris, France
3. The Amalfi Coast, Italy
4. Yellowstone National Park, Wyoming
Four of my favorite dishes
1. Ahi tuna
2. Tortellini
3. Spanakopita
4. Lechon asado (the way they make it at Alma de Cuba)
Four sites I visit daily
1. RadGeek
2. Brad Spangler
3. Kevin Carson
4. Ludwig von Mises Institute
Four places I’d rather be right now
See my answers to Four places I’ve vacationed, above.
Four new bloggers I’m tagging
Ah well, when Alexander the Great** was on his deathbed, he was asked to whom he wished to bequeath his empire. “To the strongest,” he is said to have replied. Same deal here: this meme* belongs to whoever can seize it.

* The term “meme” as here employed is intended in a metaphorical sense only, and implies no agreement with any particular semantic or cognitive theory. Offer void where prohibited by law. Side effects may include convulsions, vomiting, or instant death. If this meme lasts longer than four hours, see a praxeologist immediately.

** The term “Great” as here employed is intended simply as a historical identifier and implies no endorsement of the foreign or domestic policies of the Macedonian Empire or any of its employees, representatives, heirs, or assigns. For external use only. Contents may have settled during shipment. Keep away from children.

Posted March 6th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#03
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Melancholy Miscellany


Posted March 3rd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#02
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


From Russia With Love

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

Guess the mystery philosopher:

I was a Russian Jew by birth, but an American and an atheist by choice. In early adulthood I fled Russian tyranny to come to America, where I became involved in the fledgling libertarian movement. One of the chief libertarian newspaper writers of that era was my friend and intellectual mentor, though we later had a somewhat acrimonious break. I never held an official academic post, but I wrote widely on philosophical and political questions, favouring secularist rationalism, ethical individualism, and extreme economic and political laissez-faire. After an early flirtation with a somewhat Nietzschean version of egoism, I developed more of a natural-rights approach, drawing on the classical liberal tradition. Later in life, I annoyed many of my former associates by sharply condemning libertarianism – especially in its anarchistic form. My spouse pre-deceased me by several years.

Who am I?

Posted March 1st, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog03-06.htm#01
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Moments of Transition

Andreas Katsulas, who played G’kar so unforgettably on Babylon 5, has died.


Read Straczynski’s comments here.

Hear G’kar break your heart here. And here.

Posted February 28th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#16
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Andrews and Walker: Anarchist Classics Online

[cross-posted at Mises Blog and Liberty & Power]

Two more additions to the Molinari Online Library:

This is the first appearance of either work online.

Posted February 28th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#15
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Wieser and Smart: Austrian Classics Online

[cross-posted at Mises Blog and Liberty & Power]  Friedrich von Wieser

The latest additions to the Molinari Online Library are two early classics of the Austrian School:

Wieser’s Natural Value has been available online previously, but only in an incomplete, error-ridden, and de-formatted ASCII version. (I don’t promise that my version has no errors, only that it has fewer errors.) Smart’s Introduction to the Theory of Value, as far as I know, has never been previously available online (in either edition).

Posted February 24th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#14
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Exit to Grow in Wisdom

Lawrence Summers, Harvard’s anti-feminist, pro-militarist, pro-corporatist president, is resigning under pressure from a fed-up faculty. Seems like the best resolution to me. If Summers wants to air his views as a faculty member, that’s certainly within the bounds of academic freedom; but someone who aggressively promotes genetic fantasies about women’s innate inaptitude for science is simply the wrong person to be running an educational institution – or at least one with female faculty and students. By analogy, if you want to be a Jehovah’s Witness, go for it, but you shouldn’t expect to be put in charge of the bloodmobile. The job of a university president should be to facilitate the work of the university community, not to undermine it. (Actually I’m not even convinced that there should be university presidents – the University of Bologna got along fine without any “administration” at all – but that’s another story.)

Posted February 21st, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#13
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Spooner on Rent

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

Benjamin Tucker famously held that property in real estate depends on continued personal occupancy, so that when a landlord undertakes to rent out a plot of land or a building to a tenant, the “landlord” actually surrenders ownership to the “tenant,” who – despite whatever contract she may have signed – has no obligation, enforceable or otherwise, either to keep paying rent or to return the property at the expiration of the lease.

I think Tucker’s view on this subject is mistaken, but debating its merits is not my present concern. (For a defense of Tucker’s position, see Kevin Carson’s critique of absentee landlordism; for the contrary view, see my forthcoming reply to Carson in the next issue, 20.1, of the JLS.) Rather, for purposes of this post I want to ask a historical question: what was Lysander Spooner’s position on this issue?

It’s often assumed that it must have been similar to Tucker’s; in Egalitarianism as a Revolt Against Nature, for example, Rothbard treats the abolition of rent as part of the “Spooner-Tucker doctrine.” But while Spooner and Tucker were certainly aligned on many issues, they had some important disagreements as well – most notably on intellectual property (Spooner was pro, Tucker con) and on the ethical foundations of libertarianism (Spooner favoured natural law while Tucker favoured Stirnerite egoism). So it’s by no means a foregone conclusion that Spooner and Tucker must have agreed about rent.

Perhaps it’s assumed that Spooner and Tucker were both anti-rent because they both supported the Irish movement to resist paying rent to landlords. But in Spooner’s 1880 Revolution: The Only Remedy for the Oppressed Classes of Ireland, the only reason Spooner gives for impugning the property title of landlords in Ireland is not that the landlords have failed to maintain personal occupancy, but rather that their holdings “were originally taken by the sword” from the native cultivators – an argument perfectly consistent with Lockean/Rothbardian views on rent.

I can’t claim to have scoured every inch of Spooner’s texts for remarks on this issue, but what I have found convinces me that Spooner’s position on rent was in fact the Lockean/Rothbardian one and not the Tuckerite one at all.

So there’s my brief for dehomogenising Spooner and Tucker on the land issue. Perhaps I should add by way of clarification that I don’t mean to be offering the fact that Spooner agrees with me against Tucker about rent as any sort of argument for the truth of my position! (That should be obvious, but I know from experience that if I don’t make it explicit some insightful reader is likely to send me an email saying “So Spooner agrees with you against Tucker; so what? That doesn’t prove that he’s right! You are such a moron.”)

In any case, I agree with Tucker against Spooner about intellectual property, so it’s not as though I can consistently exalt one above the other. In his Law of Intellectual Property Spooner tries to show that if you agree with him about land you’re thereby committed to agreeing with him about copyrights and patents also. Obviously I think his arguments on that point fail, for reasons I plan to address in a future post; my line of attack would be a development of the approach I sketch here and here. But as I said above, my concern in the present discussion is not to offer a theoretical defense of any particular view about property rights, but simply to make the historical, interpretive point that Spooner’s view on rent was not the same as Tucker’s. (Well, to the extent that there’s any polemical payoff I suppose it’s this: those anarcho-socialists who grant the title of “anarchist” to Tucker and Spooner but deny it to Rothbard and other so-called “anarcho-capitalists” on the grounds inter alia of the latter’s disagreement with Tucker about land will find their position at least somewhat harder to maintain to the extent that the distance between the “saved” Spooner and the “damned” anarcho-capitalists is narrowed.)

Well, it’s 3:00 a.m. Tuesday, and my sleepless Sunday night is starting to reassert itself against the temporary reinvigoration from my Monday-afternoon nap, so I’m off to bed.

Posted February 21st, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#12
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


San Franarchy

I’m back! The conference was great – with some interesting connections made between the attempts by our authors to tame the political power of religious extremism in the 17th century, and the need to deal with militant Christian and Muslim extremism today.

I also had a marvelous time in San Francisco – wandering around Chinatown, North Beach, Fisherman’s Wharf, the Embarcadero, and the Mission District; riding the Powell Street cable car; enjoying delicious dinners (for free!) at Ponzu, The Slanted Door, and Il Fornaio; and buying obscure anarchist tomes at City Lights Bookstore (of Kerouac and Ginsberg fame) and Bolerium Books (of imperial road kill fame).

Alas, things took a less enjoyable turn on the way home, when my twice-delayed flight, which should have gotten me back to Atlanta at 7:30 last night, didn’t get me in till 6:30 this morning, leaving me in a somewhat zombified state all day today. (Happily I only had to give midterms today rather than lecture; and I’m just now somewhat refreshed from a brief nap.) But at least my twelve hours in the San Francisco airport gave me plenty of time to read some of my new books! Here’s what I’ve been reading:

Though it isn’t on anarchism and I didn’t get it in San Francisco, I also recently read and enjoyed a book of Early Stories of Jules Verne, including his novella on Peru’s colonialist heritage, The Pearl of Lima (a work clearly modeled on Victor Hugo’s novella on the Haitian slave revolt, Bug-Jargal). I was struck, though not especially surprised, by the contrast between Verne’s (relatively) sensitive and nuanced attitude toward Peruvian natives and his tiresomely stereotyped prejudices regarding Jews. (Remember, Verne also sided against Dreyfus, at least initially.) Evidently, in Verne’s eyes some oppressed peoples were more equal than others.

Posted February 20th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#11
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


From Wilderland to Western Shore

I’m off to San Francisco for a Liberty Fund conference. Topic: the oft-skipped biblical-interpretation passages in Hobbes, Spinoza, and Locke.

Back next week!

Posted February 15th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#10
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Bang Bang He Shot Me Down

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

I’m sure the running dogs of statism will be rushing to use His Excellency’s recent misadventure as another argument for increased gun control.

If so, the case will be a poor one. In the world the gun controllers are building, people like Cheney will always have access to firearms.

Posted February 12th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#09
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Moon Man

For fans of Jules Verne (about whom I’ve blogged a fair bit lately), check out Ken Gregg’s interesting post.

Posted February 12th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#08
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Who’s on First?

I’m sometimes asked why I label (or likewise why Rothbard labeled) Gustave de Molinari the “first market anarchist” or the “founder of market anarchism.” Weren’t there anarchists before Molinari who were pro-market?

Certainly there were; the clearest cases are William Godwin in England, Josiah Warren in America, and Pierre-Joseph Proudhon in France. Some would deny that these thinkers count as pro-market, since they were “socialists”; but we shouldn’t let ourselves be confused by terminology. While these thinkers’ views on property may fall short of Rothbardian purity – or, heck, even Tuckerite purity (Proudhon and Tucker definitely need some dehomogenising) – they all clearly favoured some form of private ownership and free market exchange.

So if they were anarchists who liked the market, why am I reluctant to call them market anarchists? Well, it seems to me that what Molinari pioneered, in 1849, was an explanation of how market mechanisms could replace the traditional “governmental” function of the State – protection against aggressors. If one looks to Godwin and Warren for an analogous discussion, there’s precious little on this topic at all; their solution to the problem of aggression seems to consist primarily of converting potential aggressors to anarchism. As for Proudhon, whenever he starts talking about administrative arrangements under anarchism he ends up describing centralised institutions whose difference from the monopoly State is difficult to discern.

Thus I don’t see anything properly describable as market-based anarchism (as opposed to merely market-friendly anarchism) prior to Molinari.

What’s not clear to me is how much influence Molinari exerted on the subsequent market anarchist tradition. (He certainly influenced de Puydt and possibly influenced Bellegarrigue, but de Puydt’s competing jurisdictions operate within the framework of a monopoly state, while Bellegarrigue is vague about administrative details, at least in the writings I’ve seen.) Benjamin Tucker and his associates certainly defended market anarchism in terms reminiscent of Molinari’s arguments; but while they were unquestionably familiar with and indebted to Godwin, Proudhon, and Warren, Liberty’s review of a work from Molinari’s later semi-anarchist period apparently shows no awareness of his early fully anarchist writings. So they may well have developed the same ideas independently.

Posted February 11th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#07
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Wear the Future


MOLINARI INSTITUTE T-SHIRT #1


MOLINARI INSTITUTE T-SHIRT #2


You know you want one.

Posted February 7th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#06
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Randians on the Warpath

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

Two recent Randian skirmishes:


Posted February 6th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#05
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


The Empire Victorious

The blog contest at Liberty & Power is over, and I’m pleased to announce that Austro-Athenian Empire was declared the winner in the category of “individual libertarian/classical liberal academic blog.”

To everyone who voted for me – thank you!

To everyone who voted against me – you have been declared enemies of the Empire, and my agents will be hunting you down without mercy.

Posted February 6th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#04
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Farewell and Thank You

 Coretta Scott King, 1927-2006; Betty Friedan, 1921-2006; R.I.P.

Posted February 5th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#03
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Tarzan’s Burden

I was around age 11 when I first discovered Edgar Rice Burroughs. (See his two entertaining autobiographical sketches, one true and one invented – I’ll let you decide which is which.) I believe I started off with the second and fourth Venus novels – a rather disorganised way to begin. I started writing comic books about Barsoom, Amtor, and Pellucidar, and was especially fascinated by the concept of a hollow earth (as my comments on Wally Conger’s blog show).

Unfortunately, most people know Burroughs’ work – including his most famous creation, Tarzan – only through the movie versions, and Burroughs has not been well-served by Hollywood (though hopefully the upcoming John Carter flick will be an exception); indeed, I’ve never seen any screen depiction of Tarzan, even in some of the better films, that bore any similarity to Burroughs’ character. (Who would guess from the movies, for example, that Tarzan’s dominant characteristic is intelligence – or that his first spoken human language was French?)

All this is by way of introduction to an interesting article I just came across, by F. X. Blisard, about race relations in the Tarzan novels and in Burroughs’ work generally – fairly enlightened for Burroughs’ era, it turns out, and far superior to Hollywood’s treatment. Read it here: part 1, part 2, part 3, part 4.

Posted February 3rd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#02
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Ayn Rand’s Left-Libertarian Legacy

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

Today is Ayn Rand’s birthday.

Last year, for her centenary, I wrote about Rand’s legacy for libertarians generally. This year I want to write about her legacy for left-libertarians in particular.

Rand’s legacy? For left-libertarians? Such a proposal might well engender skepticism. Sure, Rand’s critical attitude toward religion, tradition, and “family values” has sometimes led paleolibertarians to view her as a lefty; but on a broad range of other issues she is easily viewed as decidedly right-leaning. Consider:

Yes, alas, all that is true; but it’s not the whole story. There is another side to Rand’s legacy that should not be lost sight of.

It transpires, then, that there are in effect two Rands, or two strands in Rand: a left-libertarian, feminist, anti-militarist, anti-corporatist, benevolent, experimental strand, and a conservative, patriarchal, homophobic, flag-worshipping, boss-worshipping, dogmatic strand. Which strand represents the “true” Rand? Well, both of them; she just is precisely the person who tried to combine these two strands.

A better question is: which strand most accurately expresses her fundamental principles? And here it seems to me that the answer is: the left-libertarian strand. The conservative strand, as I see it, is in large part (not entirely – human psychology and intellectual development are complex matters, and I don’t mean to be offering some sort of reductionist account) an expression of Rand’s understandably hostile reaction to the Soviet environment in which she was raised. I suspect that she tended to have a knee-jerk reaction to anything (well, almost anything – not atheism, obviously, or contextual analysis) that reminded her of Soviet propaganda or was associated in any way with pro-Soviet sympathies. Hence anything that championed labour against capital, or denounced the United States as imperialistic, or otherwise savoured of left-wing critiques, was likely to trigger her ire. (Maybe this is the story with regard to art also. In the 1920s and 30s, when the Soviets were denouncing abstract art as an expression of western decadence, she liked such art and even found it liberating; in later years, living in the west where leftists had embraced abstract art, she came to detest it. Might it really be that simple? Certainly the Rand who wrote The Fountainhead was eminently equipped to answer the objections to abstract art raised by the later Rand.)

But if we leave aside the influence of anti-Soviet sentiment and simply consider in what direction a radical, contextual-analysis-oriented, secular, individualist, anti-traditionalist, anti-sacrificial libertarian ethic is most naturally developed – it’s left-libertarianism, man.

Posted February 2nd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog02-06.htm#01
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


The Rainbow and the Bridges of the Olbermann

On Wednesday I sent the following email to Keith Olbermann’s show Countdown:

On last night’s show while discussing the Katrina snafu you said that you hoped someone would think up a way for providers of governmental services to compete against each other. Actually this idea has been around for a long time and there is a whole movement of people (including your humble correspondent) advocating it; it’s called “polycentric law” and you can read about it here:

http://osf1.gmu.edu/~ihs/w91issues.html

Posted January 28th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#34
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Amica Libertas Sed Magis Amica Veritas

Once when I was 12 or so I went up to the checkout with six comic books I’d picked out, only to realise I had just enough money to buy four. So the clerk at the cash register started to pick two at random to put back, as though I would have no preference as to which four of the six to keep. I was amazed.

When I was in high school I intended to become a novelist. One of the counselors thought this was a great idea, and advised me, “take a look at which novels are the best sellers, and try to write novels like that” – as though I might want to be a novelist without having a preference for writing any particular sort of novels. Once again I was amazed.

I’m likewise amazed whenever I see the argument that “if you want to be successful in promoting libertarianism, you need to give up on feature X or feature Y” – as though someone might want to promote libertarianism without caring about promoting any particular version of libertarianism. (I’m talking about cases where feature X or feature Y is part of one’s view rather than, say, a dispensable rhetorical emphasis involved in promoting the view.)

Now perhaps I’m being uncharitable. Those who offer this argument might reply: “Look, of course we know that you prefer your version of libertarianism to other versions. But any version of libertarianism is preferable to non-libertarianism; so adopting a more marketable version of libertarianism than the one you favour will increase the odds of getting libertarian views to displace non-libertarian ones.”

But first, it’s by no means obvious that every version of libertarianism is preferable to every version of non-libertarianism. (Is Leonard Peikoff’s pro-mass-murder version of libertarianism, for example, really preferable to, say, Jon-Stewart-style liberalism?) And second, even if it were so, asking libertarians to argue for (not just vote for, but argue for) a version of libertarianism they disbelieve is asking them to engage in deception.

All of which brings me to a recent exchange between Carl Milsted and Stephan Kinsella. Milsted advises anarchist libertarians to give up their opposition to taxation and the state, on the grounds that refusing to do so “subjects us to ridicule” since “99+% of the people consider anarchy to be too risky to be attempted.” Kinsella responds by accusing Milsted of caring more about “what will sell” than about “what is true.”

Now Kinsella’s charge might seem unfair. After all, Milsted’s argument doesn’t take the form “anarchism makes libertarianism hard to sell, so let’s abandon anarchism.” Instead it takes the form “anarchism makes libertarianism hard to sell, so let’s look very closely to see whether we can find a justification for abandoning anarchism, and sure enough, I’ve found one.” The justification he finds is the principle – mistakenly attributed to Rothbard – that, allegedly, “theft is morally acceptable if all victims are paid back double.” (Kinsella mentions this principle’s similarity to Epstein’s views; I would add that it also bears some resemblance to Nozick’s compensation principle, which was thoroughly, and to my mind decisively, critiqued in the very first issue of JLS.) So isn’t it this principle, rather than the pragmatic consequences of advocating or not advocating anarchism, that is grounding Milsted’s argument?

Well, maybe. But the principle is so implausible – and, as Kinsella points out, has implications so grotesque that hardly anybody, libertarian or non, would endorse them – that it’s hard to imagine purely libertarian reasoning leading one to this principle without background pragmatic considerations offering assistance across the inferential gaps.

Posted January 26th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#33
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


How the Randians Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Statist Collectivism and Mass Death

I wish I could say it’s only the Peikoffian branch of the Randian movement that engages in this kind of malevolent tribalism, but alas.

Posted January 25th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#32
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


New Anti-IP Resource

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

A draft of Michele Boldrin and David K. Levine’s book Against Intellectual Monopoly is available online. It offers, inter alia, an interesting critique of the innovation-requires-intellectual-property argument.

Conical hat tip to Alex Singleton via Kevin Carson.

Posted January 24th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#31
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


The Problem of Pain

I can be mistaken about whether you’re in pain, but I can’t be mistaken about whether I’m in pain.

But what sort of fact is that? One natural answer – we might call it the Cartesian answer – is that it’s just a basic albeit somewhat mysterious property of self-awareness that it has a kind of luminous infallibility that other forms of awareness don’t.

Wittgenstein famously criticises the Cartesian answer. I think the Wittgensteinian criticism is correct – but I also think it’s also easily misunderstood.

Let me start by setting out what I think is the wrong way to describe the Wittgensteinian critique, because getting the wrong interpretation out on the table will ultimately be helpful in explaining the right interpretation. I’ll call the proponent of the wrong version the “pseudo-Wittgensteinian.”

So the pseudo-Wittgensteinian says: Look, if you buy the Cartesian answer then you think it’s some sort of discovery we made that we can be wrong about other people’s pain but not about our own. But there’s no fact to be discovered here, apart from our linguistic conventions. The meaning of terms and phrases like “my pain,” “your pain,” “mistaken,” and so on is determined by our rules – conventional rules – for using them. And it’s just a fact about our linguistic rules that sentences like “she’s in pain” may be answered with “how do you know?” while sentences like “I’m in pain” may not. Just as the rules of chess determine that moving a bishop diagonally is a permissible move but moving a rook diagonally is not, so the rules of our language game determine that challenging your knowledge of another’s pain is a meaningful move while challenging your knowledge of your own pain is not. So the alleged infallibility of self-awareness isn’t some deep fact about our minds; it’s just an artifact of our linguistic conventions. And so there’s no necessity to it; just as we could change the rules of chess to allow a rook to move diagonally, so we could change the rules of our language game to make epistemic access to our own pain fallible, or epistemic access to others’ pain infallible, or both.

As I say, I don’t think this answer is Wittgenstein’s answer. But Wittgenstein’s answer sounds a lot like this answer; so it’s easy to read him as saying that the infallibility of self-awareness is a fact about our linguistic conventions rather than about our mental states. But here’s where I think the difference lies. Consider: is it really true that “we could change the rules of chess to allow a rook to move diagonally”? Well, it depends what you mean by “rook.” If you mean the little wooden or plastic thingy that looks like a tower, then sure, we can make any rules we want about how that is to move. We can play checkers instead of chess with it; we can even toss the rook, in that sense of “rook,” back and forth across a net, or whack it with a stick, if we’re so inclined. But if by “rook,” you instead mean something defined in terms of the (current) rules of chess, then nothing counts as a rook except insofar as it is moved in accordance with those rules.

Analogously: we can of course mean anything we want by words like “pain” and “mine” – i.e., by those audible sounds or those visible marks. We could use “pain” to mean “chocolate cake” or “the British are coming!” In that sense, words are like chess pieces understood as little wooden or plastic thingies. But of course if we did that we would be changing what the words mean, and it’s no surprise that our linguistic conventions determine what our words mean.

Now when the pseudo-Wittgensteinian says that it’s a matter of linguistic convention whether our access to pain is infallible, she surely isn’t meaning to make merely the utterly boring observation that it’s a matter of linguistic convention whether the word “pain” – the sound or mark – refers to something to which we have infallible epistemic access, i.e., that it’s a matter of linguistic convention what “pain” means. For the Cartesian never dreamed of denying something so obvious. What the pseudo-Wittgensteinian must mean is that the word “pain,” meaning what it means, is only conventionally associated with certainty – so that a change in our linguistic conventions could make it the case that our epistemic access to our own pain is no longer infallible, without changing the meaning of the word “pain” (or the word “infallible,” or any other of the words involved).

The real Wittgenstein’s approach, as I read it, has in common with the pseudo-Wittgensteinian approach an emphasis on the fact that our linguistic rules simply don’t allow anything to count as a meaningful challenge to our awareness of our own pain. But the upshot convicts both the Cartesian and the pseudo-Wittgensteinian of the same mistake: both are implicitly assuming that such a challenge could make sense. The Cartesian treats our infallible access to our own pain as an amazing discovery about our minds, as though we might instead have discovered the opposite; the pseudo-Wittgensteinian treats such access as something rendered true by our linguistic conventions, as though our conventions might have rendered it false. And so both the Cartesian and the pseudo-Wittgensteinian see the incorrigibility of pain as grounded in something (whether in our language games or in the metaphysical nature of pain itself) that explains it and secures it – some x such that, but for that x, pain would not be incorrigible. But Wittgenstein’s point is that since – given what “pain” means in our language – no sense has been assigned to expressions like “I’m not sure whether I’m in pain,” it follows that no such x is either needed or possible; the incorrigibility of pain requires no explanation or grounding. (Those who’ve read my anti-psychologism paper will recognise that I’m offering another “rail-less” account here.)

Someone might object: “look, we know what ‘I’m in pain’ means, and we know what ‘I don’t know whether ...’ means, so how could the combined expression ‘I don’t know whether I’m in pain’ fail to have a meaning?” The answer here is that Wittgenstein accepts Frege’s Context Principle: what a word means depends on the meaning of the sentence in which it appears. Just because “angry” has a meaning in the sentence “Listening to President Bush makes me angry,” it doesn’t follow that it has a meaning in “Let’s angry some parsnips.” Likewise, just because the words “know” and “pain” make sense in a sentence like “I don’t know whether Eric is really in pain or only faking,” it doesn’t follow that they still make sense in a sentence like “I don’t know whether I’m in pain.”

(I should also note that although Wittgenstein thinks we can be mistaken about whether another person is in pain, he thinks it doesn’t make sense to suppose that we’re consistently mistaken about others’ pain. Analogously, although we can accidentally make illegal chess moves, it doesn’t make sense to suppose that all or most of the chess moves ever made have accidentally been illegal – because the practice of chess defines what’s legal. But that’s a different story we needn’t get into right now.)

I think all this is relevant to ethics. How so? Well, we only apply the term “good” to things we approve of or endorse. This might mean, as Plato perhaps thought, that goodness is a property with a mysterious hold over our will, such that we can’t recognise that something is good without thereby being moved to endorse it. (J. L. Mackie, in his book Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, even uses this idea as an argument for moral skepticism: if moral properties existed they’d have to be mighty weird, but we have no reason to believe in such mighty weirdness, so we have no reason to believe there are any moral properties.) Or one might resist this view by insisting that the alleged magnetic attractiveness of goodness is simply reducible to the conventional rule of language that we don’t call something good unless we endorse it.

Well, it’s true that it’s a matter of linguistic convention that the word “good” refers to something endorsed; after all, it’s a matter of linguistic convention that the word “good” means anything at all. But given what the word means, it’s not a matter of convention that to see the good is to endorse the good. And that’s the grain of truth in the Platonic view; but Plato’s mistake lies in thinking of the attractiveness of goodness as grounded in the metaphysical nature of goodness, when it’s not grounded in anything at all. (Of course if you want to call this ungroundedness “the metaphysical nature of goodness,” feel free, but be careful not to confuse this sort of metaphysics with the other.)

Does this dispose of moral skepticism? Not necessarily. But I think it does show that it’s not an option for the moral skeptic to suggest that all our moral judgments are or might be false; instead the skeptic has to shoulder the burden of arguing that our moral concepts don’t, or might not, make sense. (Ditto for pain; indeed, I think the best way to understand, e.g., the Christian Scientist’s rejection of the reality of pain is to take her as claiming not that our self-ascriptions of pain are false but rather that they can’t be made coherent sense of and so don’t even rise to the level of being true or false.) But I have yet to see a persuasive argument from the moral skeptic to that effect. And if our moral concepts do make sense, there can’t be any further question about whether they apply to reality. The rules that give moral terms their sense just are the rules for applying them to reality.

Posted January 23rd, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#30
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


See the Violence Inherent in the System!

Check out Norm Singleton’s latest post on the left-libertarian thread at LRC Blog. Toward the end Norm says:

I am not sure what a non-violent form of oppression is, or even if there is such a thing. Which is not to say I don’t think Roderick is right to suggest libertarians should engage these issues, merely that it confuses the issues to refer to non-state, non-violent oppression. Also, maybe some of what the left complains about as oppression is totally justified, such as an employer imposing a dress code on employees.
Well, if there can be such things as systematically stifling power relations not primarily based on violence (governmental or otherwise), I see no reason not to call these forms of oppression. Most libertarians may balk at the notion of “systematically stifling power relations not primarily based on violence” but they generally don’t have a problem with the concept when it’s dramatised in works like The Fountainhead. As Charles Johnson and I have written elsewhere:

Although its political implications are fairly clear, The Fountainhead pays relatively little attention to governmental oppression per se; its main focus is on social pressures that encourage conformity and penalize independence. Rand traces how such pressures operate through predominantly non-governmental and (in the libertarian sense) non-coercive means, in the business world, the media, and society generally. Some of the novel’s characters give in, swiftly or slowly, and sell their souls for social advancement; others resist but end up marginalized, impoverished, and psychologically debilitated as a result. Only the novel’s hero succeeds, eventually, in achieving worldly success without sacrificing his integrity – but only after a painful and superhuman struggle.
Why isn’t “oppression” a perfectly good term for what Rand is describing?

For more on the issue of nonviolent oppression, I highly recommend Marilyn Frye’s article “Oppression” (read the complete article in image format here or an incomplete version in text format here). Rand and Frye would no doubt detest each other, for a mix of good and bad reasons I reckon, but I’m happy to learn from both without offering a blanket endorsement of either.

On the issue of dress codes, it depends what’s meant by “totally justified.” If it means “just” (in the sense of “non-rights-violating”), sure – at least so far as the employer’s position is not itself the result of state intervention on his or her behalf. (Rothbard was friendly to the idea that companies that owed their wealth primarily to state patronage should become the property of their employees.) But something can be just without being justified; there’s more to what virtue demands of us than merely refraining from violating rights. Whether a dress code is justified or not will depend, I suppose, on a variety of factors, including how relevant it is for the job and how burdensome or otherwise obnoxious it is for the workers. Suppose Colonial Bank announced that all its black employees had to dress as slaves. Unjust? Nope. Unjustified? Yup.

In any case, dress codes aren’t primarily what leftists complain about on behalf of employees. They mainly complain about low salaries, lack of job security, lack of voice in management decisions, and the petty chickenshit tyrannies of bosses. I think those problems stem in part from the lack of a competitive labour market, thanks to government intervention; nonviolent oppression draws much of its support from violent oppression, and so would be much weaker in a genuine free market. (That’s the point that leftists often miss.) But I don’t think such problems are reducible without remainder to government intervention; they also depend on cultural factors that need to be combated separately. (That’s the point that libertarians often miss.)

For more musings on the “labortarian” thesis that libertarians should return to the days when they shared many of the concerns of the labour movement, see Kevin Carson here and here; Charles Johnson here, here, and here; and me here and here – as well as an upcoming issue of The Industrial Radical (which I remind you to write for).

Posted January 21st, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#29
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


The Greatest Love of All

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

More shameless self-promotion: further details about my summer seminar on the praxeological foundations of libertarian ethics have been posted here. Ah, the wonder of me.

Posted January 19th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#28
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


These Acronyms Were Brought to You By the Letter W

WWWD = What Would Dubya Do?

WWIWWD = What Would the Wobblies Do?

WWWWWD = What Would the World Wide Web Do?

Posted January 19th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#27
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


News from the Rebellion


Posted January 17th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#26
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


The Wisdom of Al Gore

Flipping channels tonight I was amazed to hear Al Gore, of all people, explaining:

Whenever power is unchecked and unaccountable it almost inevitably leads to mistakes and abuses. In the absence of rigorous accountability, incompetence flourishes. Dishonesty is encouraged and rewarded. ... It is often the case that an Executive Branch beguiled by the pursuit of unchecked power responds to its own mistakes by reflexively proposing that it be given still more power. Often, the request itself it used to mask accountability for mistakes in the use of power it already has.
Yes, Al, absolutely. But would you still believe this if you were President?

Posted January 16th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#25
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Why Do They Hate Us?

Hey, beginning logic students! Confused about the difference between “and” and “or”? Allow me to explicate:

The U.S. foreign policy promise, Iraqi version: Cooperate with us or we’ll bomb your civilian population.

The U.S. foreign policy promise, Pakistani version: Cooperate with us and we’ll bomb your civilian population.
Still confused? Yeah, me too.

Posted January 16th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#24
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


End of an Era

Oh no!

I just found out that Loompanics Unlimited is going out of business. (Conical hat tip to Wally Conger.)

For the past thirty years Loompanics has been the indispensable source of libertarian, anarchist, and counter-economic books that could find no other publisher or distributor. Sure, there was always a fair share of puerile, misogynistic, or crackpot offerings, but there was also much priceless treasure. And the book catalogues were fascinating magazines in their own right, filled with original articles.

I’m very sad to see it go.

Two slightly cheery notes to relieve the gloom: first, Loompanics is having a big 50% off sale, so at least we can load up on loot before the final eclipse. (If the links don’t work too well on that page, try this one.)

Second, in this age of on-demand publishing and online marketing, it will be easier for Loompanics-type material to get into print than it was when Loompanics was first launched. (Indeed, the Molinari Institute plans to start a book publishing program eventually, which reminds me that you should donate vast quantities of money to the Institute to speed the advent of this and other programs.)

Posted January 16th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#23
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Reunification

Brad Spangler writes: “It’s time for libertarians to stop fighting the left and take up the challenge of leading the left.” (Read the whole thing.)

Social Memory Complex says amen, but adds the caveat that we need to work on redefining the term “left” to free it of its association with state socialism.

I too say amen to Brad’s comment, but with a caveat from the other direction, as it were: we shouldn’t let talk of “leading the left” give the impression that libertarians have everything to teach, and nothing to learn from, the left.

Ever since libertarians and leftists went their separate ways, libertarians have specialised in understanding
     a) governmental forms and mechanisms of oppression, and
     b) the benefits of competitive, for-profit forms of voluntary association;
while leftists have specialised in understanding
     c) non-governmental forms and mechanisms of oppression, and
     d) the benefits of cooperative, not-for-profit forms of voluntary association.
Libertarians have a great deal to teach leftists about (a) and (b), but leftists likewise have a lot to teach libertarians about (c) and (d).

Thus I would say that the proper aim of the left-libertarian movement is both to lead the left back to its libertarian roots, and to lead libertarians back to their leftist roots. We might call this “left-libertarian reunification.”

Brad makes another valuable point: “Radicals define the moderate position,” because “as the radicals go, so do the moderates grudgingly follow in small steps.”

Posted January 16th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#22
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Happy Actual Birthday

An unjust law is a code that is out of harmony with the moral law. ... Any law that uplifts human personality is just. Any law that degrades human personality is unjust. ... One has not only a legal but a moral responsibility to obey just laws. Conversely, one has a moral responsibility to disobey unjust laws. I would agree with St. Augustine that “an unjust law is no law at all.”

– Martin Luther King, Jr.

Posted January 15th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#21
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Write a Letter to Cory Maye

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

How can you help Cory Maye – who from the facts I’ve seen shouldn’t even be in prison, let alone facing execution?

Charles Johnson offers some suggestions: write letters (to the governor, to the newspapers), use your blogs (write posts, display banners), contribute to the defense fund.

In a recent email Lawrence Krubner suggests you might also want to write a letter to Maye himself, to boost his morale; info here.

Posted January 14th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#20
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Postcards from Cimmeria

A number of Robert E. Howard’s classic heroic-fantasy works are being reissued in new editions, including Bran Mak Morn, Solomon Kane, and all the original Conan stories in three volumes titled The Coming of Conan, The Bloody Crown of Conan, and The Conquering Sword of Conan.

The chief advantage of these new editions is the wealth of stunningly beautiful illustrations; the books are worth getting just for the pretty pictures alone! (Thank you, Del Rey.)

If the only image you associate with this material is that of Arnold Schwarzenegger, do yourself a kindness and check these out; the Morn, Kane, and Crown titles let you browse some of the pics online at Amazon.

Posted January 14th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#19
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


A Lefter Shade of Thick

The discussion of my recent posts Left Behind, Ties that Bind, and Alienation, Assassination, and Inflation continues on LRC blog. Here are some excerpts, with comments from your humble correspondent.


Posted January 14th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#18
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


A Night in Old Vienna

I first read the libretto of Die Fledermaus when I was about ten or so.

Why? I believe it was because I’d encountered a bat-like creature called a “flittermouse” in the book Merry-Go-Round in Oz – written, as it happens, by a woman whose grandson would years later become a friend of mine in grad school – and so the word “Fledermaus” caught my eye. (I recall that I picked up Die Fledermaus along with the libretto of a rather less celebrated operetta titled Help, Help, the Globolinks! – an alien-invasion comedy for kids.)

I must be one of the few people to have first encountered Die Fledermaus through the libretto rather than the music – though I must share that distinction with Johann Strauss at least. I was rather charmed by the libretto (I especially liked the exchange between the two characters each pretending to be French), but it wasn’t until I caught a performance on tv a few years later that I first discovered the music and became truly entranced. (I never did hear the music for Globolinks, though it’s probably available.)

For years afterward, tv performances of Die Fledermaus were a standard New Year’s ritual for me. But in recent years it hasn’t been on at New Year’s; I don’t know whether it’s gotten generally less popular or whether it’s just that Alabama has more meager PBS offerings than other places I’ve lived.

But now I’ve finally gotten my Fledermaus fix for this season; I saw it in live performance last night at the Opelika Civic Center, performed by the Russian troupe
Helikon. Although I have to say that I wasn’t crazy about this particular staging (neither the acting nor the set was particularly impressive; the non-singing portions of the story were streamlined to the point of plot-unintelligibility; the commedia dell’ arte clowns, while delightful, were distracting and out of place; and the pacing was broken by placing the intermission in the middle of Act 2), seeing it live was a delight nonetheless. And oh, that music!

Posted January 13th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#17
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


Alienation, Assassination, and Inflation

A couple of comments I’ve received on my post Ties That Bind:

Max Schwing (of Karlesruhe, Germany) writes:

I usually agree with your essays and get a bunch of new ideas or approaches to known subjects. However, I must disagree with your assessment in the post “Ties that Bind.” Perhaps it is that way in the US, but in Germany and France, where socialism prevails in disguise of “social democracy,” you can’t separate the leftist agenda of “anti-market-ism” and “anti-war” and on other issues it gets even worse. The problem is that they can identify problems, but they always seek the state as a solution (even those that call themselves “Anarchists,” although they have different names for it). They truly are afraid of free markets and especially laissez-faire capitalism. And it even gets worse on issues like sexism/racism. I won’t say that the conservatives are any better (again rallying for nationalism in Germany). It is hard to convince die-hard socialists or Marxists that free markets are a solution. They often don’t think of people as capable of living their lives without help from a 3rd institution. At least, this is the impression I got during talks with many local socialists or Greens. And while the Social Democrats are at least accepting the idea that marketplaces exist for their own benefit, many individuals leaning even more to the left have even stronger feelings against anything economically, that is not supervised by an almighty and good institution.

I don’t know whether the US has a different kind of socialists, who accept the idea of market economy and only think the state is rudimentarily necessary (and I don’t want to use the term capitalism here). In Germany and old Europe in general, as they call it nowadays, economics is a field of study that is not deeply respected and often seen as dubious and of no practical relevance. Perhaps it is this deep hatred against something which is believed to be imported from the English, that disallows leftists to regard the market as an option.
Well, what does it mean to say that one “can’t separate” these issues? If it means that leftists generally don’t separate them, that’s regrettably true, but I don’t see how it’s an objection to what I said, because on the contrary it is what I said. The distinction I drew between two different senses of “tied” is precisely the distinction I would now draw between the analogous two senses of “can’t separate.”

Max wonders whether socialists in the U.S. are more pro-market than they are in Europe. I don’t know whether they are; but I can’t see that anything in my argument turns on their being so. It’s just as true here as in Europe that many on the left tend to see markets as a cause of, and the state as a solution to, a vast array of social problems. But the claim I was defending in my original post was not that people who care about patriarchy etc. aren’t anti-market (many of them are) or don’t regard the two types of concern as linked (many of them do); rather my claim is that the two types of concern shouldn’t be linked for us. The assumption on the part of leftists that the two types of concern logically go together is a mistake on their part, and I was warning my fellow libertarians against committing the same mistake from the other side.

Max’s reaction to my second post is reminiscent of Norm’s response to my first post. And this is true of responses I’ve received privately from other folks as well. (You know who you are....) Everyone seems to be writing me to say “But Roderick, you don’t seem to realise that most of these left-wingers are anti-market.” How do I not realise it? I said it. I’m puzzled that I’m being taken to have denied it.

Max notes that many European leftists have disdain for economics because they see it as “imported from the English.” It might be useful, then, for pro-market propagandists in Europe to focus on the authentically European roots of market thought. Pro-market “capitalist” economist thinkers on the Continent include Bastiat, Molinari, Mises and Hayek; pro-market “socialist” economic thinkers on the Continent include Proudhon and Oppenheimer. All these thinkers were quite critical, albeit in varying ways and to varying degrees, of the English classical tradition in economics, which Austrians in particular argue represents in many ways a deviation from the subjectivist economics first developed on the Continent.

Max also adds a postscript which contains a possible spoiler for fans of the new Galactica, so click here to read it.

[As for assassination as a tool of foreign policy (a question raised in the aforementioned postscript) I tend to think it would be morally preferable to standard military measures (since it targets the ruler instead of the oppressed subjects), but don’t much fancy it as a governmental power in addition to standard military measures. I’ve written about this here.]

On a related subject, some libertarians tell me that libertarian outreach to the left is hopeless and pointless, a well that was drained dry by Rothbard in the 1960s. But this post by Joel Schlosberg is a good argument to the contrary.

Speaking of Joel Schlosberg, he also writes me on this topic:

One quick point I want to make with regards to your recent debate over knee-jerk anti-leftism:

It should be pointed out that the concept of alienation in particular, while nowadays usually associated with Marxism, is no more Marxist than, say, anti-imperialism is.

There’s a good discussion of this in Erich Fromm’s The Sane Society, where he refers to examples of people dealing with the problem of alienation from across the gamut of the political spectrum – even staunch conservatives. In particular, during the nineteenth century, “The prognosis of the decay and barbarism into which the twentieth century will sink was made by people of the most varied philosophical views. The Swiss conservative, Burckhardt; the Russian religious radical, Tolstoy; the French anarchist, Proudhon, as well as his conservative compatriot, Baudelaire; the American anarchist, Thoreau, and later his more politically minded compatriot, Jack London; the German revolutionary, Karl Marx – they all agreed in the most severe criticism of the modern culture and most of them visualized the possibility of the advent of an age of barbarism.’ Fromm specifically refers to the individualist analyses of alienation by Thoreau and Proudhon, quoting the latter’s description of a free market between laborers: “reciprocity, where all workers instead of working for an entrepreneur who pays them and keeps the products, work for one another and thus collaborate in the making of a common product whose profits they share amongst themselves. ” – and goes on to note that it is “essential for him that these associations are free and spontaneous, and not state imposed, like the state-financed social workshops demanded by Louis Blanc.” Incidentally, in the book he also quotes (and italicizes for emphasis) Aldous Huxley’s statement in an introduction to Brave New World that “Only a large-scale popular movement toward decentralization and self-help can arrest the present tendency toward statism.” (and who indeed saw the increase of statism as tending to a totalitarian direction – one of my favorite left-wing anti-statist quotes).

There’s also Chris Sciabarra’s book list <http://www.nyu.edu/projects/sciabarra/notablog/archives/000487.html> that includes Bertell Ollman’s Alienation: Marx’s Conception of Man in Capitalist Society along with many libertarian books, including Ayn Rand’s Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal (probably one of the few such lists that includes both books!)
I would add only that (“even”!) Rand was much more sympathetically interested in the topic of alienation than the dismissive discussion in Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal might imply. What are The Fountainhead and Ideal if not extended meditations on the forces of alienation in modern society and how to overcome them?

In other mailbox news, Adem Kupi comments on my post Platonic Bailments. I don’t think we disagree, really; though I would want to stress that it’s not fiat money per se but the absence of competition that is the real problem. If issuers of fiat money had to compete against issuers of commodity-based money – or even against other issuers of fiat money – their ability to inflate would be severely curtailed. When one issuer enjoys a monopoly and is thus freed from the discipline of the market, the incentive to inflate becomes very strong.

That, incidentally, is why I think the euro is such a bad idea. It’s not that under a free market Europe would be better off with many currencies than with one; perhaps the opposite is true. But it’s certainly better off with many currencies allowed than with only one allowed. (As an Austrian, I define competition in terms of freedom of entry, not market share.)

Posted January 11th, 2006
Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#16
Comment

Write for The Industrial Radical
Support the Molinari Institute


SUBMIT to The Industrial Radical

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power and the Molinari News Page]

The Molinari Institute is pleased to announce that later this year we will begin publishing a magazine of radical libertarian political and social analysis titled The Industrial Radical. (“Industrial” in Herbert Spencer’s sense, “Radical” in Chris Sciabarra’s sense.) We hereby invite submissions. (See our submissions guidelines and copyright policy. Also note that The Industrial Radical is a popular magazine, not an academic journal; formal, scholarly articles might be more appropriately submitted to, oh, um, say, the Journal of Libertarian Studies.)

Submissions may be of any length, from a brief paragraph to a lengthy essay; we also welcome a diversity of perspectives, whether you dance to the music of F. A. Hayek, Murray Rothbard, Benjamin Tucker, Henry George, or Emma Goldman. Previously published pieces are fine so long as they meet our copyright requirements. We plan to publish themed issues (see theme topics and submission deadlines here), but please don’t refrain from sending us an article just because it doesn’t fit an upcoming theme; the themes are designed to inspire submissions, not discourage them.

Please pass the word, by blogpost or email, to anyone you think might be interested in contributing. (Advance subscriptions are available too.)

Posted January 10th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#15

Comment


Ties That Bind

My friend Norm Singleton (who happens to be Ron Paul’s legislative assistant) has a post on LRC blog today commenting on a post of mine last month on what I called “knee-jerk anti-leftism” in some libertarian circles.

Norm says he largely agrees with me, but does note one point of disagreement:

I think Roderick underestimates (to say the least) the extent to which rhetoric about “patriarchy, white supremacy, and alienation” is tied to attacks on capitalism and western civilization, not just the warfare state, and thus should be rejected by libertarians.
Well, what does it mean to say that such rhetoric is “tied” to an anti-market (I find the term less misleading than “anti-capitalist”) agenda? If it means that many of those who use such rhetoric are anti-market, and regard market society as a major cause of such problems as “patriarchy, white supremacy, and alienation,” that’s certainly true. It’s equally true, of course, that many leftists regard market society as a major cause of militarism and imperialism. Does that mean that leftist antiwar rhetoric is “tied” to an anti-market agenda and so should be condemned by libertarians? Presumably Norm would agree with me that the answer is no in the war case; so why not equally so in the former case?

Or does Norm mean that concerns about patriarchy, white supremacy, etc.unlike antiwar concerns – are intrinsically tied to an anti-market agenda? If so, I deny it; on the contrary, these concerns were originally libertarian concerns, and libertarians’ alienation from such concerns, and from their “left-wing” heritage generally, throughout much of the 20th century is a historical anomaly (resulting, I believe, from the understandable, though to my mind disastrous, libertarian alliance with conservatives against the genuine menace of state socialism).

As Charles Johnson points out in his comments at the Molinari Symposium last month, there may be certain values that, while not “strictly entailed by the non-aggression principle,” are nevertheless “a causal precondition for implementing the non-aggression principle in the real world” because a libertarian society might be unlikely “to emerge, or survive over the long term, or flourish, without the right bundle of commitments.” Moreover, rejection of such values, while not logically inconsistent with libertarianism, might “undermine or contradict the deeper reasons that justify libertarian principles in the first place.” Charles and I have argued previously that opposition to patriarchy is indeed one such value (and it’s not hard to see how our arguments there could be extended to concerns about racism, etc.). The fact that many of those who currently espouse such concerns have an anti-market agenda (or more precisely, an animus against something called “capitalism,” in which genuine free markets and state-sponsored corporate mercantilism are murkily conflated) is no proof that these concerns are inherently un-libertarian, any more than the fact that (switching from left to right) most supporters of tax cuts these days are also supporters of drug prohibition and the like proves that tax cuts are a bad thing.

Posted January 10th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#14

Comment


Platonic Bailments

Would fractional-reserve banking be objectionable in a genuine market context?

I don’t think so. If all participants are fully informed, it’s not fraudulent; and in the absence of central banking and legal tender laws, competition among banks should keep inflationary expansion in check.

But many libertarians (see, e.g., this article) argue that fractional-reserve banking is still problematic because it requires (or its legitimacy would require) more than one person having title to the same piece of property. Imagine a streamlined case of a 50% reserve bank with two customers, Emma and Voltairine. Each deposits one florin. The bank keeps one of the florins in its vault and invests the other. Who owns the florin in the bank’s vault? By calling the florin a “deposit” and assuring each customer that she may withdraw her deposit at will, the bank is attempting to treat both Emma and Voltairine as each having full title to the single florin – which is impossible. All that Emma and Voltairine have really done is to lend some money to the bank; neither one has any money in the bank.

So runs the argument; and fractional-reserve “deposits” are accordingly contrasted with bailments, in which an item of property is deposited with a warehouse for safekeeping, and the warehouse is not permitted to lend the item out. If I place a florin in the warehouse, then I can truly say I have a florin in the warehouse. Fractional-reserve banking, its libertarian critics argue, is a confused attempt to combine incompatible categories, a bailment and a loan, into a single concept.

In my view, the argument I’ve just cited depends on an excessively sharp line between loans and bailments – in brief, that its conception of a bailment is excessively “Platonic” – in the same way that the neoclassical conception of perfect competition, the Objectivist conception of legal finality, and the marginal-productivity argument against feminist labour activism are “Platonic.”

The difference between the florin I lend and the florin I deposit as a bailment is, supposedly, that I retain full right of use and disposal over the bailment. But in what sense is that really true? Let’s say that I place my florin with Acme Warehouse for safekeeping. Does that mean I can reclaim my florin whenever I want? Suppose Acme Warehouse’s business hours are 9 to 5; can I reclaim my florin at midnight? Clearly not; I must wait till the next morning.

Do I now have full title to the florin, or not? Well, you can say, if you like, that I have full title but that it’s temporarily encumbered in certain respects; or you can say that title is now shared between me and the warehouse – that title has been decomposed into a bundle of rights, some going to Acme and others being retained by me. I don’t much care which verbal formula we choose so long as we keep track of who’s got rights to do what, how and when, with what.

Now complicate the story still further: my contract with Acme stipulates that they’re not liable for loss of my property due to theft, fire, or flood. So now they not only have no legal obligation to return my florin immediately, but there are also circumstances in which they have no legal obligation to return my florin, or even its equivalent, at all – though so long as the florin is not stolen or destroyed they still have to return it.

At this point the distinction between a bailment and a loan has gotten a good deal less sharp. My contract with my bank may specify circumstances under which they don’t have to give me my deposit immediately, and further circumstances under which they don’t have to give it to me at all. The difference is mainly a matter of degree. (There’s a further complication here, which is that in the case of a bank deposit it’s not the actual physical coin but any coin of the same quantity that they owe me; but if I place a living organism as bailment it’ll be composed of different particles when I get it back too.) It’s only the idealised, unrealistic, Platonic conception of a bailment as something you have total right to get back whenever you want it, a condition that rarely applies to real-world bailments, that gives the distinction an illusion of purchase.

The question is sometimes raised whether it’s fraudulent to count fractional-reserve deposits among one’s assets. Well, I don’t know. Those who think it isn’t seem to regard it as okay to count bailments as assets. But which has more claim to be one of my assets – a fractional-reserve deposit at a bank with a 5% chance of going bankrupt, or a bailment at a no-responsibility-for-loss warehouse in a high-crime district where the chance of loss due to theft is 10%?


In other news: Not only am I geekier than Tom Woods and Stephan Kinsella, but I’m also 1.2 times as geeky as Aeon Skoble (who scored 29.98028%) and 1.15 times as geeky as Anthony Gregory (who score 31.46%). Pretty scary.

Posted January 9th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#13

Comment


Booted and Spurred

I used to be a libertarian, and an anarchist.

As recently as yesterday, in fact.

But I’ve had a revelation concerning the traditional roles of king and subject, lord and serf, master and slave.

After all, civilised man spent millennia developing these roles. Whether you view the roles as having resulted from aeons of evolution or through an act of God, it remains that our biological makeup makes traditional hierarchical roles work. In general, the servile class are happiest toiling in the fields or hauling enormous blocks to build monuments, while rulers are happiest luxuriating in wealth, putting on enormous pageants, pontificating about social order, or waging war against neighbouring districts.

Our biology supports this further by the fact that children respond best – are happiest and healthiest – in the stable presence of such roles during their growing years. After all, our little future serfs need to have patterns of deference and hard work inculcated early on, while our little future rulers need role models from whom to emulate the wrinkled lip and sneer of cold command.

None of this is to say that serfs can’t occasionally be employed in a supervisory capacity – or that rulers can’t get an occasional kick out of dressing up like peasants and miming a bit of labour, like the Hungarian courtiers hoing in the vineyard, or Marie Antoinette disporting herself as a shepherdess at the Petit Trianon, or our own Prince President rolling up his sleeves and playing ranch. (After all, as Queen Victoria is reputed to have said, “It must be fun to work, because it’s so much fun to watch other people work.”) But in moderation, by all means.

The source of my newfound enlightenment? This piece by Brad Edmonds.

Posted January 9th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#12

Comment


Mayeday

Hey bloggers – don’t let the Cory Maye story slide into your archives; add a banner or button to your blog to keep the story (and thus hopefully Maye) alive. I made my own, but Laura Denyes over at What Is Liberalism? has a whole page full.

Posted January 8th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#11

Comment


Geekier than Thou

More miscellaneous materials:

Watch this space.

I mean, without blinking.

Posted January 7th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#10

Comment


Support Libertarian Forum

The Mises Institute is considering publishing a high-quality 1300-page print copy of Murray Rothbard’s 1969-1984 periodical Libertarian Forum in a limited run, and is soliciting charitable donations to lower the volume’s selling price. If you’re interested in contributing, you can do so here. If you’re wondering whether you should be interested in contributing, here’s what fellow left-libertarian blogospheroid Wally Conger has to say about Libertarian Forum:

Murray’s Forum reported in “real time” the libertarian break with the conservative Young Americans for Freedom (YAF) in 1969. It presented month-by-month Murray’s flirtation with the New Left and his efforts (and eventual failure), between 1969 and 1971, to build a Left-Right anti-state/anti-war coalition. Shortly after his break with Goldwater Republicans and his union with the New Left, the great Karl Hess wrote some wonderful and highly radical columns for LF in its first two years of publication; Karl’s gradual split with Murray over style and strategy is quietly documented in these early issues. Many philosophical and tactical arguments were fought and documented in the pages of The Libertarian Forum. For example, early battles about launching a “Libertarian Party” vs. non-political libertarian action took place in the Forum. Besides Rothbard and Hess, other celebrated contributors to LF included Leonard Liggio, Jerome Tuccille, Roy Childs, Butler Shaffer, and Walter Block. ...

A longtime dream has become reality. Tons of long-out-of-print Rothbard writings are now available for us to pursue. The entire glorious goddamn history of This Movement of Ours is now at our fingertips! This latest gift from the Mises Institute to radical Rothbardians may be the most valuable treasure we�ll see in another decade or more.
Check out the online version for yourself, here.

(I’d cross-post this on L&P but it seems to be suffering an ontological deficit at the moment.)

[Update: L&P appears to have recovered now; I’ve posted a note there inviting readers to Kill Some Trees for Liberty!]

Posted January 6th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#09

Comment


Miscellaneous Roundup

Various stuff:

More later!

Posted January 6th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#08

Comment


Raising Cain

Just a reminder: the best science-fiction series currently on tv returns from hiatus tomorrow night, as Ron Moore’s Pegasus (or savage-commentary-on-Abu-Ghraib) arc continues.

George Bush won’t be watching. Will you?

Posted January 5th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#07

Comment


Vote for Mises!

[cross-posted at Mises Blog]

The first round of voting in the libertarian academic blog contest at Liberty & Power is over; Mises Blog won a plurality, but not yet an absolute majority, in the best group blog category (and your, ahem, humble correspondent likewise won a plurality, but not yet an absolute majority, in the individual blog category). So now run-off voting is starting.

If you want to push Mises Blog (and, er, anyone else) to victory, vote here.

Remember, if you don’t vote, the terrorists win!

Posted January 5th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#06

Comment


JLS 19.4: What Lies Within?

[cross-posted at Liberty & Power]

The latest issue (19.4) of the Journal of Libertarian Studies is out this week, with lots of cool new stuff: Alexander Groth critiques the Bush administration’s democracy-building policy in Iraq; William Anderson and Candice Jackson argue that the Wall Street prosecutions of the late 1980s contributed to the recession of the early 90s, as well as promoting the interests of the corporate elite; Piet-Hein van Eeghen offers a rebuttal to Robert Hessen’s defense of the corporation; Joseph Becker reproduces the Amicus Curiae brief he submitted in the Kelo eminent domain case; Randy Barnett and J. H. Huebert debate the concept of governmental legitimacy; Stephen Cox reviews Robert Mayhew’s book on Ayn Rand’s HUAC testimony; and Tom Woods reviews Alejandro Chafuen’s book on Scholastic economics.

Read a fuller summary of 19.4’s contents here.

Read summaries of previous issues under my editorship here.

Read back issues online here.

Subscribe here.

High time-preference? No problem – in a dandy new feature, if you subscribe now you’ll receive a PDF copy of the latest issue immediately. (The Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics offers this feature also.)

Posted January 5th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#05

Comment


Shadow Boxing

As I write this, several different major news channels are covering the recent Sago mining disaster and asking loudly “what went wrong?”

But it turns out that by “what went wrong?” they mean not “what caused the explosion?” but “how did the miners’ families get misinformed about who had survived?”

Now don’t get me wrong – the misinformation snafu is unspeakably gut-wrenching. And if, as some reports suggest, the mining company knowingly let families go on for three hours celebrating the alleged survival of people the company knew were dead, that’s truly unconscionable. (According to this story, “families were not told of the mistake until three hours later ... because officials wanted to make sure all of their information was right”; according to this one, company officials “didn’t want to put the families through another rollercoaster.” What cowardly, paternalistic bullshit.)

But all the same, isn’t the story of what caused the explosion – and whether, for instance, the company bears any responsibility – even more important than the story of why the families were falsely told that their loved ones had survived? In the final analysis, the primary horror is the actual deaths of those twelve people, and the three hours of false hope for their families, while horrific, are a secondary horror. Yet nearly all the investigation I’ve seen so far focuses – loudly, intensively, hysterically – on the secondary horror and pays virtually no attention to the primary.

Our news media appear more interested in analysing perceptions of reality than they are in analysing reality itself. Is that’s because they’re corporate-controlled, and so seek to downplay serious criticisms of management in favour of more superficial criticisms? Or is it just a more general superficiality endemic to contemporary culture as a whole? I don’t know, but either way it’s dysfunctional journalism.

[Of course there’s an occasional exception here and there, though predictably offering statist rather than labortarian solutions.]

Posted January 4th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#04

Comment


How I Found Threedom in an Unthree World

As a complement to recent posts by fellow left-libertarian blogospheroids Brad Spangler and Black Guile on the possible structures of legal/defensive and other associations under market anarchism, I’d like to recommend a 1995 piece by my friend Phil Jacobson, Three Voluntary Economies. Tolle, lege.

Posted January 4th, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#03

Comment


Anarchist in the Chimney

I know this is a week late – or 51 weeks early – but I can’t resist posting this great pic that B. K. Marcus created:


Posted January 2nd, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#02

Comment


Anarchy in New York

Happy new year to all!

 Angela Gheorghiu I’m back from NYC, where our department interviewed thirteen candidates, all quite good philosophers; it looks like we’ve got a strong prospect of adding a top-notch colleague this year.

The Molinari Society also held its second annual symposium there. I thought it was a very successful (and well-attended) meeting; check out Charles’ excellent commentary on the papers by Narveson and Ross. (I also enjoyed getting a chance to meet with some of my fellow left-libertarian blogospheroids.)

Between my departmental and Molinarian duties I didn’t get much chance to get out into the city except for meals, but I can recommend lunch at Dean & DeLuca, dinner (albeit molto costoso) at Gramercy Tavern, and dreamy hot chocolate at La Maison du Chocolat.

Last night I watched the Lincoln Center New Year’s concert, with Angela Gheorghiu (see pic on right) singing selections from Italian opera – including my favourite aria, Puccini’s Un bel di, which represents, for me, the highest musical expression of ecstatic, unbearable longing that the human spirit has yet produced. I’m also looking forward to watching the annual New Year’s Johann Strauss concert from Vienna later tonight. Radetzky March!

Watch this space for some exciting announcements, in the next week or two, about the Molinari Institute’s projects for the coming year.

Posted January 1st, 2006

Permalink: praxeology.net/unblog01-06.htm#01

Comment




If philosophy is not relevant to your life,
change your life.


Blogosphere of the Libertarian Left
Ring Owner: Thomas Knapp Site: Blogosphere of the Libertarian Left
Free Site Ring from Bravenet Free Site Ring from Bravenet Free Site Ring from Bravenet Free Site Ring from Bravenet Free Site Ring from Bravenet
Site Ring from Bravenet

Check out earlier posts:
Austro-Athenian Imperial Archives.

Back to Praxeology.net.
Back to Molinari Institute.

Sick of this website? Try someone else’s.


   



I support individual rights