B U R E A U O F P U B L I C S E C R E T S |
1
Chatels article on Godards film [Breathless] in Socialisme ou Barbarie #31 can be characterized as film criticism dominated by revolutionary concerns. The analysis of the film assumes a revolutionary perspective on society, confirms that perspective, and concludes that certain tendencies of cinematic expression should be considered preferable to others in relation to the revolutionary project. It is obviously because Chatels critique thus sets out the question in all its fullness, instead of merely debating various questions of taste, that it is interesting and calls for discussion. Specifically, Chatel finds Breathless a valuable example supporting his thesis that an alteration of the present forms of culture depends on the production of works that offer people a representation of their own existence.
2
A revolutionary alteration of the present forms of culture can be nothing less than the
supersession of all aspects of the aesthetic and technological apparatus that constitutes
an aggregation of spectacles separated from life. It is not in its surface meanings that
we should look for a spectacles relation to the problems of the society, but at the
deepest level, at the level of its function as a spectacle. The relation
between authors and spectators is only a transposition of the fundamental relation between
directors and executants. . . . The spectacle-spectator relation is in itself a
staunch bearer of the capitalist order (Preliminaries Toward
Defining a Unitary Revolutionary Program).
One must not introduce reformist illusions
about the spectacle, as if it could be eventually improved from within, ameliorated by its
own specialists under the supposed control of a better-informed public opinion. To do so
would be tantamount to giving revolutionaries approval to a tendency, or an
appearance of a tendency, in a game that we absolutely must not play; a game that we must
reject in its entirety in the name of the fundamental requirements of the revolutionary
project, which can in no case produce an aesthetics because it is already entirely beyond
the domain of aesthetics. The point is not to engage in some sort of revolutionary
art-criticism, but to make a revolutionary critique of all art.
3
The connection between the predominance of the spectacle in social life and the
predominance of a class of rulers (both being based on the contradictory need for passive
adherence) is not a mere clever stylistic paradox. It is a factual correlation that
objectively characterizes the modern world. It is here that the cultural critique issuing
from the experience of the self-destruction of modern art meets up with the
political critique issuing from the experience of the destruction of the workers movement
by its own alienated organizations. If one really insists on finding something positive in
modern culture, it must be said that its only positive aspect lies in its
self-liquidation, its withering away, its witness against itself.
From a practical standpoint, what is at issue
here is a revolutionary organizations relation to artists. The deficiencies of
bureaucratic organizations and their fellow travelers in the formulation and use of such a
relationship are well known. But it seems that a completely conscious and coherent revolutionary
politics must effectively unify these activities.
4
The greatest weakness of Chatels critique is precisely that he assumes from the
start, without even alluding to the possibility of any debate on the subject, that there
is the most extreme separation between the creator of any work of art and the political
analysis that might be made of it. His analysis of Godard is a particularly
striking example of this separation. Having taken for granted that Godard himself
remains beyond any political judgment, Chatel never bothers to mention that Godard did not
explicitly criticize the cultural delirium in which we live and did
not deliberately intend to confront people with their own lives.
Godard is treated like a natural phenomenon, a cultural artifact. One thinks no more about
the possibility of Godard having political, philosophical or other positions than one does
about investigating the ideology of a typhoon.
Such criticism fits right into the sphere of
bourgeois culture specifically within its art criticism sector
since it obviously participates in the deluge of words that camouflages every single
aspect of reality. This criticism is one interpretation among many others of a work
on which we have no hold. The critic assumes from the beginning that he knows better
than the author himself what the author means. This apparent presumptuousness is in
fact an extreme humility: the critic so completely accepts his separation from the
artistic specialist in question that he despairs of ever being able to act on or with him
(which would obviously require that he take into consideration what the artist was
explicitly seeking).
5
Art criticism is a second-degree spectacle. The critic is someone who makes a spectacle out of his very condition as a spectator a specialized and therefore ideal spectator, expressing his ideas and feelings about a work in which he does not really participate. He re-presents, restages, his own nonintervention in the spectacle. The weakness of random and largely arbitrary fragmentary judgments concerning spectacles that do not really concern us is imposed upon all of us in many banal discussions in private life. But the art critic makes a show of this kind of weakness, presenting it as exemplary.
6
Chatel thinks that if a portion of the population recognizes itself in a film, it will be able to look at itself, admire itself, criticize itself or reject itself in any case, to use the images that pass on the screen for its own needs. Let us first of all note that there is a certain mystery in this notion of using such a flow of images to satisfy authentic needs. Just how they are to be used is not clear. It would first of all seem to be necessary to specify which needs are in question in order to determine whether those images can really serve as means to satisfy them. Furthermore, everything we know about the mechanism of the spectacle, even at the simplest cinematic level, absolutely contradicts this idyllic vision of people equally free to admire or criticize themselves by recognizing themselves in the characters of a film. But most fundamentally, it is impossible to accept this division of labor between uncontrollable specialists presenting a vision of peoples lives to them and audiences having to recognize themselves more or less clearly in those images. Attaining a certain accuracy in describing peoples behavior is not necessarily positive. Even if Godard presents people with an image of themselves in which they can undeniably recognize themselves more than in the films of Fernandel, he nevertheless presents them with a false image in which they recognize themselves falsely.
7
Revolution is not showing life to people, but bringing them to life. A
revolutionary organization must always remember that its aim is not getting its adherents
to listen to convincing talks by expert leaders, but getting them to speak for themselves,
in order to achieve, or at least strive toward, an equal degree of participation. The
cinematic spectacle is one of the forms of pseudocommunication (developed, in lieu of
other possibilities, by the present class technology) in which this aim is
radically unfeasible. Much more so, for example, than in a cultural form such as the
university-style lecture with questions at the end, in which dialogue and audience
participation, though subjected to rather unfavorable conditions, are not absolutely
excluded.
Anyone who has ever seen a film-club debate has
immediately noticed the dividing lines between the leader of the discussion, the
aficionados who regularly speak up at every meeting, and the people who only occasionally
express their viewpoints. These three categories are clearly separated by the degree to
which they have mastered a specialized vocabulary that determines their place within this
institutionalized discussion. Information and influence are transmitted unilaterally, from
the top to the bottom, never from the bottom to the top. Nevertheless, these three
categories are quite close to one another in their common confused powerlessness, as
spectators making a show of themselves, in relation to the real dividing line between them
and the people who actually make the films. The unilaterality of influence is still more
strict in relation to this division. The considerable differences among the various
spectators mastery of the conceptual tools of film-club debates are ultimately
diminished by the fact that those tools are all equally ineffectual. A film-club debate is a
subspectacle accompanying the projected film; it is more ephemeral than written criticism,
but neither more nor less separated. In appearance a film-club discussion is an attempt at
dialogue, at social encounter, at a time when individuals are increasingly isolated by the
urban environment. But it is in fact the negation of such dialogue since these people have
not come together to decide on anything, but in order to hold a discussion on a
false pretext and with false means.
8
Leaving aside its external effects, the practice of this type of cinematic criticism
immediately presents two risks to a revolutionary organization.
The first danger is that certain comrades might
be led to formulate other criticisms expressing their different judgments of other films,
or even of this one. Beginning from the same positions concerning the society as a whole,
the number of different possible judgments of Breathless, though obviously not
unlimited, is nevertheless fairly large. To give just one example, one could make a
critique just as talented as Chatels, expressing exactly the same revolutionary
politics, but which would attempt to expose Godards own participation in an entire
sector of the dominant cultural mythology: that of the cinema itself (shots of the
tête-à-tête with the photo of Humphrey Bogart, cut to the Café Napoléon). Belmondo
on the Champs-Élysées, at the Café Pergola, at the Rue Vavin intersection
could be considered as the image (largely unreal, of course, ideologized) that
the microsociety of Cahiers du Cinéma editors (and not even the whole generation
of French filmmakers who emerged in the fifties) projects of its own existence; with its
paltry dreams of flaunted subspontaneity; with its tastes, its real ignorances, but also
its cultural enthusiasms.
The other danger would be that the impression
of arbitrariness given by Chatels exaltation of Godards revolutionary value
might lead other comrades to oppose any discussion of cultural issues simply in order to
avoid the risk of lacking in seriousness. On the contrary, the revolutionary movement must
accord a central place to criticism of culture and everyday life. But any examination of
these phenomena must first of all be disabused, not respectful toward the given modes of
communication. The very foundations of existing cultural relations must be contested by
the critique that the revolutionary movement needs to really bring to bear on all aspects
of life and human relationships.
GUY DEBORD
1961
Pour un jugement révolutionnaire de lart,
written in February 1961, first appeared in Notes Critiques: bulletin de
recherche et dorientation révolutionnaires #3 (Bordeaux, 1962).
This translation by Ken Knabb is from the
Situationist
International Anthology (Revised and Expanded Edition, 2006). No copyright.
Bureau of Public Secrets, PO Box 1044, Berkeley CA 94701, USA
www.bopsecrets.org knabb@bopsecrets.org