- published: 23 Jun 2016
- views: 190
Science is a systematic enterprise that creates, builds and organizes knowledge in the form of testable explanations and predictions about the universe.
Contemporary science is typically subdivided into the natural sciences which study the material world, the social sciences which study people and societies, and the formal sciences like mathematics. The formal sciences are often excluded as they do not depend on empirical observations. Disciplines which use science like engineering and medicine may also be considered to be applied sciences.
During the middle ages in the Middle East, foundations for the scientific method were laid by Alhazen. From classical antiquity through the 19th century, science as a type of knowledge was more closely linked to philosophy than it is now and, in fact, in the West the term "natural philosophy" encompassed fields of study that are today associated with science, such as physics, astronomy and medicine.
In the 17th and 18th centuries scientists increasingly sought to formulate knowledge in terms of laws of nature. Over the course of the 19th century, the word "science" became increasingly associated with the scientific method itself, as a disciplined way to study the natural world. It was in the 19th century that scientific disciplines such as physics, chemistry, and biology reached their modern shapes. The same time period also included the origin of the terms "scientist" and "scientific community," the founding of scientific institutions, and increasing significance of the interactions with society and other aspects of culture.
This series explores scientific realism, the view that our best scientific theories accurately describe the world and that we should believe in the entities and properties postulated by them. In the video, I first define scientific realism more precisely; then I outline various alternatives to realism; and I finally I briefly discuss two popular variations on realism, entity realism and structural realism.
I examine the no-miracles argument for scientific realism, which claims that the best explanation for the success of science is that our best scientific theories are approximately true.
Scientific realism is, at the most general level, the view that the world described by science is the real world, as it is, independent of what we might take it to be. Within philosophy of science, it is often framed as an answer to the question "how is the success of science to be explained?" The debate over what the success of science involves centers primarily on the status of unobservable entities apparently talked about by scientific theories. Generally, those who are scientific realists assert that one can make valid claims about unobservables (viz., that they have the same ontological status) as observables, as opposed to instrumentalism. Points Covered: IS THERE SUCH A THING AS A GENE? ARE SPECIES REAL? WHAT DOES SCIENCE IMPLY? WHAT DOES SCIENCE MEAN? QUESTIONS OF REALITY ANTI-REAL...
Entity realism, most famously defended by Ian Hacking, is the view that we should believe in the unobservable entities postulated by scientists, but be skeptical of scientific theories. In this video I examine Hacking's "manipulation argument" for entity realism, which claims that we must believe in those unobservable entities that we can use as tools for studying other phenomena.
PART 1: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=t5VfB... Please read the description & be polite. Share if you like this video. Part two of an animated video essay that tries to answer whether there is a biological basis for gender. REFERENCES: http://milanvuckovic.com/References-i... CREDITS: Copyediting by my lovely sister Jelena Vuckovic Narrated by Natascha Szabo Music by http://musicincloud.com Illustration, Animation, Writing by me. Website: http://www.milanvuckovic.com Twitter: http://twitter.com/Wukish Typo at the end: Instead as it should be "Johns" I wrote "John"
Paul Dicken (Cambridge) gives a talk at the MCMP Workshop on Carnap titled "Tolerance & Voluntarism". Carnap's dissolution of the scientific realism debate rests upon two central claims: the first regarding the appropriate logical reconstruction of a scientific theory; the second, a background conception of the nature of ontological disputes. Recent work has focused on the first of these claims; in this talk Paul Dicken discuss the second, and relates it to similar moves made by van Fraassen in his own articulation of empiricism.
Scientific realism is, at the most general level, the view that the world described by science is the real world, as it is, independent of what it might be taken to be. Within philosophy of science, it is often framed as an answer to the question "how is the success of science to be explained?" The debate over what the success of science involves centers primarily on the status of unobservable entities apparently talked about by scientific theories. Generally, those who are scientific realists assert that one can make valid claims about unobservables as observables, as opposed to instrumentalism. This video is targeted to blind users. Attribution: Article text available under CC-BY-SA Creative Commons image source in video
An explication of the metaphysical, semantic, and epistemic commitments of scientific realism
The underdetermination of theory by data is the claim that every currently accepted theory has rivals that are empirically equivalent, i.e. that make the same claims about the behaviour of the observable world. For instance, there is a physical theory that doesn't postulate electrons but that is just as compatible with the evidence as the theory we accept. So, we should not believe in the truth of currently accepted theories. This video explains the underdetermination argument in detail and then examines various problems for it, including non-empirical virtues, confirmation holism, and the theory-ladenness of observation.
What is SCIENTIFIC REALISM? What does SCIENTIFIC REALISM mean? SCIENTIFIC REALISM meaning & explanation. Scientific realism is, at the most general level, the view that the world described by science is the real world as it is, independent of what it might be taken to be. Within philosophy of science, it is often framed as an answer to the question "how is the success of science to be explained?" The debate over the success of science in this context centers primarily on the status of unobservable entities apparently talked about by scientific theories. Generally, those who are scientific realists assert that one can make valid claims about unobservables (viz., that they have the same ontological status) as observables, as opposed to instrumentalism. Scientific realism involves the two b...
Video 600 at Carneades.org! The last musical commemorative video was on problems with arguments for the existence of God, now here's one about some of the problems with arguments for scientific realism. Including the Problem of Induction, The Problem of Underdetermination, and The New Riddle of Induction. Sponsors: Daniel Helland, Will Roberts, Dennis Sexton, and Carl Green. Thanks for your support!
This video examines Arthur Fine's natural ontological attitude (NOA), a position designed to be a minimalist compromise between realism and antirealism.
In this video I introduce structural realism, the view that we should be skeptical of what our best theories tell us about unobservable entities, but be realist about the structural or mathematical claims.
Many antirealists rely on the distinction between observables and unobservables, since they assert that science gives us knowledge of the former, but not the latter. In this video, I examine the distinction, and I consider some of the arguments realists have used to try to undermine its significance.
This video examines Kyle Stanford's argument from unconceived alternatives, which essentially combines the pessimistic induction and underdetermination arguments. The argument from unconceived alternatives begins with the claim that over the history of science, there were equally good alternatives to past-accepted theories that past scientists failed to conceive of. So, there are probably equally good alternatives to currently accepted theories that modern scientists fail to conceive of. Hence we should not believe that currently accepted theories are true.
The pessimistic induction is the primary argument against scientific realism. It claims that since many of the best scientific theories of the past have been rejected, we should expect that many of the best scientific theories we currently hold will be rejected in the future. Hence, we should not believe that our best scientific theories are true. This video develops the pessimistic induction in more detail and then examines various ways that scientific realists might respond.
Science has changed the ways we think of, and act on, the world. But do we really understand the relation between scientific theories and the world? Are there different perspectives on the world? How can it be that science, a characteristically human and social endeavour, yields successful predictions and fruitful explanations? What is the role of mathematics in shaping the structure of explanation in science? How do the various theories and disciplines hang together in crafting the scientific image of the world? Is this image a product of synthesis or rivalry between theories? Can we be, or indeed ought we be, confident about the scientific image of the world? Can the history of science teach us how to do better science and how to limit or enhance the cognitive aspirations of modern scien...
Michael Friedman (Stanford) gives a talk at the MCMP Workshop on Carnap titled "Carnap's Logico-Mathematical Neutrality between Realism and Instrumentalism". In this talk, Friedman discusses the evolution of Carnap's treatment of theoretical terms from the late1930s to his mature work on the Ramsey sentence formulation of scientific theories in the late 1950s and 1960s. He concentrates on Carnap's use of this device to remain completely neutral between scientific realism and instrumentalism. A central point of discussion is his commitment to a purely logico-mathematical interpretation of the quantified existential variables in the Ramsey sentence. Far from being a desperate or ad hoc maneuver, Friedman argues that this is essential to Carnap's point of view and, in particular, to the way i...
Invited lecture at the conference of the Gesellschaft für Wissenschaftsphilosophie GWP on 10 March 2016 at Düsseldorf University