Benutzereinstellungen

Kommende Veranstaltungen

International | History of anarchism

Keine kommenden Veranstaltungen veröffentlicht

“(Re)Constructing a Global Anarchist and Syndicalist Canon

category international | history of anarchism | debate author Saturday August 31, 2013 06:49author by Lucien van der Walt Report this post to the editors

a response to Robert Graham and Nathan Jun on ‘Black Flame'

This article defends the argument that anarchism/syndicalism emerged in the 1860s, as a libertarian form of socialism, opposed to social and economic hierarchy/inequality, favouring international class struggle and revolution, from below, for a self-managed, socialist, stateless order; it defends the necessity using a truly global history and analysis, placing the colonial and postcolonial world, and a wide range of mass movements, centre-stage, in order to grasp the "canon" of texts/thinkers/theories that must be ‘regarded as authoritative for anarchist thought and practice or especially significant in the historical development of anarchism’. It rejects claims that anarchism is a timeless "orientation" existing outside of contexts and classes, and demonstrates the methodological and analytical problems that arise from such approaches, including tautology, assertion and selective use of evidence.
200pxblack_flame_cover.jpg


(Re)Constructing a Global Anarchist and Syndicalist Canon

a response to Robert Graham and Nathan Jun on ‘Black Flame'

'Anarchist Developments in Cultural Studies', special issue on 'Blasting the Canon', No. 1 (2013), pp. 193-203.


Robert Graham's and Nathan Jun's thought-provoking interventions in this special issue on 'Blasting the Canon', regarding Michael Schmidt's and my Black Flame: The Revolutionary Class Politics of Anarchism and Syndicalism (2009), is welcomed. It is a pleasure to engage two thoughtful writers, and their considerations on the anarchist canon - i.e., the texts/thinkers/theories that (as Jun argues) should be 'regarded as authoritative for anarchist thought and practice or especially significant in the historical development of anarchism'.

GRAHAM'S AND JUN'S CRITICISMS - AND MY CORE RESPONSE

Black Flame made a wide range of arguments - about, for example, the social basis of anarchist peasant uprisings, the movement's anti-colonial/anti-imperialist struggles, approaches to gender and unionism, struggle for the city etc. It has, of course, also spurred debates on anarchist (and syndicalist) theory, history and canon - such debate was one of its stated intentions (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009: 26-27).

The argument that is at issue with Graham and Jun is a fairly small part of Black Flame - the claim that anarchism (and its offshoot, syndicalism) is a distinctly modern phenomenon, born in the international socialist/ working class movement-specifically, the First International (1864-1877).

Here, in debates with Marxists and others, anarchism emerged as a distinct current, centred on the Alliance of Socialist Democracy: core members included Bakunin, Kropotkin and Malatesta. Anarchism was a libertarian form of socialism, opposed to social and economic hierarchy/inequality, favouring international class struggle and revolution, from below, for a self-managed, socialist, stateless order; syndicalism is one anarchist strategy (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009: 71, 170).

Graham objects, claiming that Black Flame's approach is 'narrow' and 'extraordinary' (by excluding certain trends), 'circular' in approach, contradictory (for supposedly insisting that anarchism be 'internally coherent,' while tolerating an incoherent 'socialism' encompassing Marxism and anarchism), and closed to 'significant departures or modifications' or 'refinement' (thus, 'dogma').

Jun claims it is circular, with a 'No True Scotsman' fallacy (setting arbitrary, shifting standards for inclusion into 'anarchism'). He rejects its (supposed) claim that anarchism is 'whatever the mainstream' of 'historical anarchism' accepted (since this might leave out other 'anarchist' views). He claims this is like asking a medieval European Catholic for a general survey of Christianity.

Both favour a vague (they say, 'broad') definition: for Graham, this means the 'possibility of anarchist doctrines arising independently in different eras and circumstances,' with anarchism having 'different schools, currents and tendencies.' Jun is more sweeping: 'anarchism' is not a 'doctrine,' but an 'orientation' 'throughout human history,' while not admitting this entails 'mass excommunications.'

I suggest, however, that these are serious misrepresentations of the Black Flame methodology, claims and coverage - Schmidt and I provide a historically-based argument that tracks the rise of anarchism (and syndicalism), summarises its key claims, traces its evolution and spread, analyses its key debates and moments - this is a fairly standard social science approach, not an exercise in arbitrary boundary setting. And, rather than being 'narrow', it uses a truly global history and analysis, placing the colonial and postcolonial world, and a wide range of mass movements, centre-stage.

Secondly, I demonstrate that Graham's and Jun's alternative approaches are far from satisfactory: both claims for multiple 'anarchisms' are simply assertions, resting on a priori positions that lack a clear methodological rationale or empirical basis, and that are constructed in ways rendering any falsification impossible. Neither provides reasoned grounds, nor evidence, for the supposed superiority of their alternative definitions.

Both authors, in short, manifestly fail to apply to their own approaches the same standards of rigour they demand from Black Flame. I submit that a historical, as opposed to a speculative approach, is more justified, and more fruitful.

RESPONSE: A HISTORICAL AND SOCIOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY

Graham and Jun dispute dating anarchism to the 1860s.

It is a matter of record, however, that the anarchist movement appeared as something new to its contemporaries, rivals, and adherents; with this appearance, anarchism first became the topic of scholarly enquiry, police investigation, and media attention (Fleming 1979: 17-19). Even writers favouring exceedingly loose definitions of 'anarchism' concede that 'anarchism' did not previously exist as a 'political force' (see, for example, Joll 1964: 58, 82, 84; Woodcock 1975: 136, 155, 170) - as, so indeed, does Jun, with his allusion to 'historical anarchism' (is there a different kind?).

The very question of whether there were earlier or 'different schools, currents and tendencies' of anarchism (Graham), or an anarchist 'orientation' 'throughout human history' (Jun) could not even be posed before this moment.

It is, then, anachronistic to represent this new, specifically, consciously 'anarchist' movement (and its syndicalist branch) as but one in a number of anarchist 'schools' 'throughout history.'

It was, and is, one of several more-or-less libertarian 'currents,' including socialist variants like autonomia (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009: 71-71). But to conflate these very different approaches with anarchism is unnecessary.

It also requires gutting the 'anarchist' movement of its specificities, while forcing the others into a single 'anarchist' category. And to make the effort to include Stirner, Zerzan, etc. into 'anarchism' has little real justification (besides a sort of dogmatic convention), yet is analytically costly.

By contrast, Black Flame consciously undertakes defining 'anarchism' (and thus, considering its ideology, history and canon) through a broad, global, representative overview of the history of this new worldwide historical and social phenomenon through examining a wide range of cases.

Building on the Age of Revolutions, located in the 'capitalist world' and the working class and socialism 'it created' (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009: 96), anarchism was 'simultaneously and transnationally' constituted by a radical network in North Africa, Latin America, and Europe (van der Walt and Hirsch 2010: liv). It then expanded globally, its first mass formations including Cuba, Mexico, Spain, and the United States.

By focusing on this movement, and taking a global view, Black Flameabstracts the core, shared features of its ideology, it's often misunderstood relationship with syndicalism, unpacks its major debates, divisions and developments, and its core social features - for example, the class character of its urban mass base.

This historical and sociological approach forms the basis for the conclusion Graham so hotly rejects: there 'is only one anarchist tradition, and it is rooted in the work of Bakunin and the Alliance' (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009: 71).

To describe this methodology as 'completely circular' (Graham), or as entailing a 'No True Scotsman' fallacy, or 'excommunications' (Jun), is a complete caricature, a failure to take seriously the core analysis Schmidt and I developed.
Contra Graham, moreover, Black Flame does not require that anarchism be reduced to 'self-described anarchists': it only requires ideological and organisational lineage. The IWW thus fits in the broad anarchist tradition; Stirner does not. It does not require that anarchism be 'internally coherent' (Graham), but merely claims that it was; this was a description.

There is no contradiction between a focused, precise definition, and a rich, nuanced, and broad account; the bulk of Black Flame provides a detailed history of the anarchist/syndicalist tradition, past and present.

RESPONSE: 'NARROW' - OR GOING GLOBAL?

Graham's charge that Black Flame has a 'narrow' approach is unconvincing.

Black Flameis perhaps the only truly global, non-Eurocentric survey of the theory and history of anarchism (and syndicalism), covering 150 years, and the only thorough survey of the tradition's internal debates, again with a global - not a 'narrow'- view. Indeed, it is precisely this scope that makes Black Flame peculiarly central to any serious debate on the meaning of 'anarchism' and its canon.

This is radically different to the narrowly North Atlantic framing that dominates the standard English-language surveys - due credit must be given to Joll, Woodcock, and Marshall for their pioneering works, but it cannot be denied they almost entirely ignored the world outside of (only parts of) Western Europe and North America. [1]

Compounding this profound imbalance, such works discuss at length obscure Western figures like Stirner, whose historical importance is trivial, and links to anarchism doubtful. This problem continues today, with marginal Americans like Rothbard, Zerzan, etc., constituting common fare in 'standard' surveys-whilst major figures like Liu, Flores Magón, J.C. Mechoso, Shin, Szabó, Thibedi, etc. are (at best) passing asides.

But with a worldwide view, trivialities in the West fade away in the light shed by truly important moments elsewhere. It is, then, rather peculiar to present Black Flame as 'narrow,' because it has a global sense of perspective.

Yet Graham continues: Black Flame has a problematic focus on 'the more narrow' world of 'class struggle anarchism.'

What exactly is 'narrow' about this world? It is, by any measure, far larger and more influential than any other contender for the 'anarchist' label; a focus on it is necessary, not 'narrow.'

This is the anarchism of towering figures, from insurrectionists (who Jun incorrectly assumes are excluded from Black Flame) like Galleani, to mass anarchists and syndicalists like Bakunin, Chu, Durruti, Goldman, Gutarra, Kim Jwa-Jim, Kropotkin, Makhno, Malatesta, Ōsugi, Rocker, and every historically important anarchist/syndicalist formation, from the Argentinean FORA and Voz de la Mujer, to Spain's CNT and Mujeres Libres, to the global IWW, South Africa's ISL/IWA, the Hunan Workers' Association, FAU/OPR-33, the Korean Ůiyŏltan, etc.

What 'school' of significance is lost by this focus? This is the force that activated revolutions in Spain, Ukraine, and Manchuria, and demonstrated anarchism was a means to change the world.

RESPONSE: 'DOGMA' OR LIVING TRADITION, CENTRAL TODAY?

Does Black Flame's focus somehow turn 'anarchism from a living tradition into a historical relic or dogma' (Graham)? No, since 'class struggle anarchism' (his term) has a rich, powerful history, and is also a 'living tradition'.

This is the tradition represented today by such key examples as the Spanish CGT and CNT, the Chilean FEL, Brazilian FARJ and Uruguayan FAU, the IWA/AIT, Egyptian LSM and other Africans, Anarkismo.net, the Greek rebels, and innumerable local groups and projects worldwide.

Notions popularised by certain academic texts - that worker-peasant anarchism has been superseded or overwhelmed by a post-1945 'new anarchism' (e.g., Woodcock, 1975) - are highly misleading, even for the West today.

Graham worries that a strict definition will mean that 'significant departures or modifications' will entail exclusion from 'anarchist status.' But every definition implies exclusion. Example: Russian 'anarchist' Bill Shatov's 'modifications' included, as Petrograd Bolshevik police chief in 1918, crushing anarchists (Bryant 1923). Must he perpetually retain 'anarchist status'?

Graham notes that some figures in the anarchist tradition (like Landauer) drew on other ideas (like Tolstoy). Black Flame's point, however, is that what a tradition shares constitutes its defining features, the parameters for 'refinement.' (And Landauer, Tolstoy aside, was an anarchist, who died for the Munich councils revolution.)

RESPONSE: ONE, TWO, THREE MANY "ANARCHISMS"?

Of course, there are probably libertarian elements in all cultures, religions and historical periods (and most modern political ideologies).

But are these all anarchist? Graham and Jun insist they are, and claim this approach has support from 'notable members' of 'historical anarchism' like Kropotkin and Rocker.

This latter claim is indeed true - but does not resolve the matter.

Is this not precisely the methodological error that Jun claims of Black Flame : asking a medieval Catholic for a survey of Christianity? Further, if anarchism arises 'independently in different eras and circumstances,' or 'throughout history,' why should Kropotkin have decisive weight? But if Kropotkin does, then why should his movement's politics not define the parameters of anarchism?

Yet Graham and Jun must invoke Kropotkin and Rocker, since it would be obviously anachronistic (and futile) to consult the works of those outside Kropotkin's tradition (e.g., Lao, Winstanley, Godwin and Stirner) for opinions on the general history of 'anarchism'.

Graham and Jun are also engaging here in a rather selective reading, skipping over Kropotkin's and Rocker's writings that make claims identical to Black Flame: anarchism as new, revolutionary, socialism (e.g., Kropotkin 1927: 46, 289-290; Rocker [1938]1989: 23-24, 34-35). It was, indeed, Kropotkin - and not Black Flame, as Jun suggests - who termed Stirnerism 'misanthropic bourgeois individualism', opposed to anarchism's 'communist sociability' (van der Walt and Schmidt 2009: 47-48).

What Graham and Jun also miss is that Kropotkin and Rocker were increasingly involved in manufacturing, for the controversial, embattled, anarchist movement, a legitimating propaganda mythology. This centred on precisely the claim that 'anarchism' existed 'throughout history' that Jun favours.

This myth-making was only possible once anarchism had emerged in the 1860s - it started around 40 years later. It is a claim to antiquity by a new movement, no more evidently true than equivalent nationalist myths. Both anarchist and nationalist myths have an obvious political function, but they are analytically misleading and often demonstrably false: Kropotkin's work in this genre was marked by contradictory claims and rather dubious readings of past trends.[2]

While many are (rightly) sceptical of nationalist mythologies, anarchist mythology continues to have a firm grip. Yet rather than interrogate such claims, many activists and scholars compound the problem by grouping widely different libertarian (and not so libertarian) strands into 'anarchism', sometimes by selecting an (arbitrary) group of writers (e.g., Eltzbacher's 'seven sages' approach: [1900] 1960), sometimes by creating vast compendiums of anything vaguely libertarian (Marshall [2008] starts with prehistory).

But this sort of exercise requires anachronistic, selective readings of the past, and such exceedingly vague (and often shifting) definitions of 'anarchism' as to render the term meaningless. For example, bringing Stirner into the same category as Bakunin requires eliding great differences, effectively reducing anarchism to 'negating the state' (Eltzbacher [1900] 1960: 189, 191, 201).

Two major problems then arise.

First, the boundaries such an exercise requires are necessarily shaky. For example, if anarchists are those who merely 'negate the state', they must include Marxist-Leninists seeking the state's 'withering away' (e.g., Mao [1949] 1969: 411), and neo-liberals opposed to statism (e.g., Thatcher, 1996). Since neither trend appears in most surveys of anarchism (except Marshall 2008: xiii, 517-518, 560), their exclusion is arbitrary and/or a de facto admission of the stated definition's fallacy.

Either way, the loose definition is unjustifiable, lacking clear criteria for inclusion and exclusion.

RESPONSE: ON METHODOLOGY AND ALTERNATIVES

Secondly, the arbitrary nature of the loose approach to studying 'anarchism' is exposed. An approach that seeks to assimilate as much as possible to 'anarchism' - presenting 'anarchism' not as a concrete historical phenomenon, but as multiple 'doctrines arising independently' (Graham) or an 'orientation' 'throughout history' (Jun) - must start from a preset definition of anarchism in such terms by the writer. This definition is not tested, but assumed true; it is freed from the possibility of falsification.

Or, it must start from an arbitrary selection of cases, from which the definition is developed (e.g., Eltzbacher [1900] 1960). The problem here is that the selection lacks justification besides anecdote, convention, or personal preference (see van der Walt and Schmidt 2009: 35). The basis for the category is thus itself unreasonable; its boundaries end up equally so.

When Graham insists that anarchism has many 'schools', he fails to provide a reasoned basis for this assertion. Having insisted Black Flame has a 'completely circular' methodology, Graham simply asserts his claim, and then finds data that fits. When the claim is disputed, he can invoke the data thus generated, as evidence to support the claim's veracity, thereby presenting alternatives as 'narrow' - a tautology.

Jun asserts, also without serious grounds, that 'anarchism' exists 'throughout human history.' Once this is taken as true, it is easy enough to find an anarchist 'orientation' everywhere. The problem is that the definition rests upon nothing solid. Jun's story of the medieval Catholic's limitations reveals his assumptions: anarchism self-evidently exists universally; disagreement is evidence of intolerant 'excommunication' or parochial ignorance.

But the basis for the superiority, even validity, of Jun's definition is never initially established.

To return to Jun's medieval Catholic: it is well-established that the Christian Church first appeared two thousand years ago, attracting police, public, and scholarly attention; also that Catholicism was one of its main branches. By contrast, it is hardly self-evident that 'anarchism' has existed 'throughout history', or that the movement of Bakunin, Kropotkin, Kim, Makhno, Mechoso, Thibedi et al. was merely one isolated branch.

RESPONSE: THE MEANING OF A WORD

And what do Graham and Jun mean by 'anarchism'? For Graham, a 'doctrine' wanting society 'without government', or 'formal structures of hierarchy, command, control and obedience' (Graham 2005: xii-xiv). For Jun, a loose 'orientation', fusing 'radical antiauthoritarianism and radical egalitarianism', opposing 'morally unjustifiable ... authority and inequality', and 'unnatural' or 'arbitrary' inequality, coercion or domination.

These are rather different claims, and in neither case is their validity obvious. Why is either better than that of Black Flame or one another? Is anarchism a 'doctrine', several 'doctrines' or an 'orientation'? Opposed to hierarchy or inequality?

There is no way of really resolving these issues, since this is discussion of a priori assertions. And these are also replete with ambiguities: Is informal hierarchy acceptable to Graham's anarchists, or 'obedience' to agreed norms or essential 'control'? In Jun's case: what of 'morally' justifiable inequality, or the coercion and domination that is neither 'arbitrary' nor 'unjustified', like the military actions of the 1936 Durruti Column?

And there is, again, the problem of arbitrary inclusion/exclusion. Both Graham and Jun include in their 'anarchist' gallery, figures that demonstrably do not conform to either definitions, such as Stirner - who rejected any constraints on individual's right to 'take' by 'might' whatever they wanted, regardless of 'justice', 'truth' and 'equality' (Stirner [1844] 1907: 200, 339, 421, 472).

And here we come full circle on the problems of vague definitions.

RESPONSE: SOME NOTES ON ARGUMENTS BY LABELLING

Graham claims that insisting that anarchism has definite historical referents is 'analogous to reducing Marxism to canonical figures and texts'; he speaks of Black Flame as promoting 'dogma', while Jun invokes spectres of 'mass excommunications'.

Such points are rather unpleasantly framed, tainting Black Flame with a scent of heresy-argument-by-labelling that does not take us anywhere.

Graham's own anthology work, after all, is a definite attempt to construct a canon of 'figures and texts'; Jun, too, admits that all political traditions entail some exclusions. If this means 'dogma' or 'excommunication', the charge must apply to Graham and Jun as well.

CONCLUSION: A CLASS STRUGGLE, GLOBAL CANON - AND WHY

The issue is not, then, whether anarchism has definite 'canonical figures and texts', but which merit inclusion. Vague claims about the nature of anarchism, developed through weak methodologies, cannot provide an adequate basis, since they entail deeply flawed definitions.

For its part, Black Flame's approach suggests the need to throw overboard spurious canons like the 'seven sages', and to instead develop a historically-based, global canon, an accurate reflection of anarchism (and syndicalism) as a historical and contemporary current.

This must necessarily include Bakunin and Kropotkin, and while Stirner, Tolstoy and Thatcher have no justified place, figures like Goldman, He Zhen, Infantes, Landauer, Liu, Flores Magón, Makhno, Mechoso, Osugi, Rouco Buela, Shin, Szabó, and Thibedi must surely be serious candidates for canonical status.


AUTHOR: Lucien van der Walt works at Rhodes University, South Africa. He is the author (with Michael Schmidt) of Black Flame: The Revolutionary Class Politics of Anarchism and Syndicalism (2009), and the editor (with Steve Hirsch) of Anarchism and Syndicalism in the Colonial and Postcolonial World, 1880-1940 (2010). He has published widely on labour and left history and theory, and political economy. Involved in union education and working class movements.


NOTES:
[1] Woodcock (1975) gave Latin America 3 pages, ignoring Africa, Asia, Australasia, and most of Eastern Europe; Joll (1964) gave the rest 9 pages; Marshall (1998) gave 2 of 41 chapters (33 of 706 pages) to Asia and Latin America.
[2 ] For example, his 1905 'Anarchism' (in Kropotkin 1927) deploys quite contradictory definitions: anarchism as ancient philosophy (287-288), as 'first formulated' in the 1790s (289-290), as new, 19th-century, revolutionary socialism (285-287), as a scheme for peaceful reform (290-291) etc.

REFERENCES
Bryant, L. 1923. Mirrors of Moscow. New York: Thomas Seltzer.
Eltzbacher, P. [1900]1960. Anarchism. London: Freedom.
Fleming, M. 1979. The Anarchist Way to Socialism: Elisée Reclus and Nineteenth-Century European Anarchism. Lanham, MD: Croom Helm/Rowman Littlefield.
Graham, R., ed. 2005. Anarchism: A Documentary History of Libertarian Ideas, Vol. 1: From Anarchy to Anarchism, 300 CE to 1939. Montréal: Black Rose.
Joll, J. 1964. The Anarchists. London: Methuen and Co.
Kropotkin, P. 1927. Kropotkin's Revolutionary Pamphlets. New York: Dover.
Mao Zedong. [1949] 1971. "On the People's Democratic Dictatorship." Selected Readings from the Works of Mao Tsetung. Peking: Foreign Languages Press.
Marshall, P. 1998. Demanding the Impossible: A History of Anarchism. New York: Harper Perennial.
Rocker, R. [1938] 1989. Anarcho-syndicalism. London: Pluto Press.
Stirner, M. [1844] 1907. The Ego and His Own. New York: B.R. Tucker.
Thatcher, M. 1996. "Speech at Poznan Academy of Economics," July 4: http://www.margaretthatcher.org/document/108362.
Van der Walt, L. and S.J. Hirsch. 2010. "Rethinking Anarchism and Syndicalism: The Colonial and Post-colonial Experience, 1870-1940," in Lucien van der Walt and S.J. Hirsch, eds., Anarchism and Syndicalism in the Colonial and Postcolonial World, 1870-1940. Leiden: Brill.
Van der Walt, L. and M. Schmidt. 2009. Black Flame: The Revolutionary Class Politics of Anarchism and Syndicalism, Vol. 1.: Counter-Power. Oakland: AK Press.
Woodcock, G. 1975. Anarchism, rev. edn. London: Penguin.

PDF of this article: http://lucienvanderwalt.files.wordpress.com/2013/06/van...e.pdf

Verwandter Link: http://wp.me/p34LBU-aL
author by Wayne Price - personal opinionpublication date Sun Sep 01, 2013 11:14author address author phone Report this post to the editors

As usual, I find Lucien's comments to be incisive, although I feel hampered by not having at hand the material he is responding to. Lucien and Michael have done important work in showing that revolutionary anarchism was not limited to the poorer nations of Europe but has been a world-wide phenomenon.

My question is to what extent there is a real argument and to what extent it is a dispute over definitions. Lucien holds (1) that the trends he calls anarchist are part of "several more-or-less libertarian 'currents,'" That is, he does not deny that there is and has been a broad stream of "libertarian" movements and thinking, but he does not find it useful to call it all "anarchist." And (2) he holds--as does every other historian I have ever read--that the modern anarchist movement began in the 1860s with Bakunin and his co-thinkers. At the most, one may argue that this movement was immediately preceded by and influenced by Proudhon and his mutualist followers, but the anarchist movement clearly took off with the Bakuninists.

As with the application of any definition to real historical processes, there are bound to be peripheral cases which do not clear fit in or out of the definition. For example the US "individualists" who were pro-markets but (in their heads anyway) anti-capitalists and pro "socialist." Black Flame would exclude them but I would not. I also find somewhat quirky Black Flame's inclusion of some anti-anarchist Marxists, such as Deleon, in the current, because he (truely) influenced the syndicalist movement. But they do not cover the minority trend within Marxism which was anti-state and anti-authoritarians (e.g. council communists).

The question of boundaries is significant today--as opposed to a dispute over history--because so many people currently accept the historical goals of anarchism but reject the class-struggle, revolutionary, approach of the founders of the movement. I are prepared to say that they are outside of the mainstream of the historical anarchist movement, and--more importantly--that I think that they are wrong, but I do not find it useful to say that they are not "anarchists."

author by nestor - 1 of Anarkismo Editorial Grouppublication date Sun Sep 01, 2013 14:02author address author phone Report this post to the editors

The full contents index for "Anarchist Developments in Cultural Studies", No. 1 - 2013, with links to the various articles, can be found here: http://anarchist-developments.org/index.php/adcs/issue/current

Graham's article can be found here: http://anarchist-developments.org/index.php/adcs/article/view/78/91

Jun's article is here: http://anarchist-developments.org/index.php/adcs/article/view/74]

author by Lucien van der Waltpublication date Sun Dec 15, 2013 05:57author address author phone Report this post to the editors

As always I appreciate Wayne's comments.

However, Wayne's argument seems to shifting between some (of his) more immediate pragmatic concerns (is it "useful" to exclude such-and-such and so-and-so?) with some larger (and in my view, rather more important and interesting) issues (like: what exactly is "anarchism" anyway?).

Well, I leave aside for now the pragmatic issue.

The larger point, and I think Wayne, you're missing this, is that the claim "that the modern anarchist movement began in the 1860s with Bakunin and his co-thinkers" and "clearly took off with the Bakuninists" is specifically denied by a large body of writers (among them, those I debated in this piece), for whom anarchism can be found all over the place and for whom the movement that started in the 1860s is really not so central at all.

Best wishes
Lucien

 
This page can be viewed in
English Italiano Deutsch



cached database error: - No database connections
(cached errors will attempt auto recovery within 5 minutes)

The site may be undergoing difficulties due to heavy load please try again later!


Warning: mysqli_fetch_row() expects parameter 1 to be mysqli_result, string given in /var/www/html/objects/sqllayer.inc on line 400

International | History of anarchism | en

Wed 15 May, 14:12

browse text browse image

Sorry, no stories matched your search, maybe try again with different settings.



cached database error: - No database connections
(cached errors will attempt auto recovery within 5 minutes)

The site may be undergoing difficulties due to heavy load please try again later!


Warning: mysqli_fetch_row() expects parameter 1 to be mysqli_result, string given in /var/www/html/objects/sqllayer.inc on line 400
Sorry, no stories matched your search, maybe try again with different settings.



cached database error: - No database connections
(cached errors will attempt auto recovery within 5 minutes)

The site may be undergoing difficulties due to heavy load please try again later!


Warning: mysqli_fetch_row() expects parameter 1 to be mysqli_result, string given in /var/www/html/objects/sqllayer.inc on line 400
Sorry, no press releases matched your search, maybe try again with different settings.
© 2005-2024 Anarkismo.net. Unless otherwise stated by the author, all content is free for non-commercial reuse, reprint, and rebroadcast, on the net and elsewhere. Opinions are those of the contributors and are not necessarily endorsed by Anarkismo.net. [ Disclaimer | Privacy ]