A
syllogism ( – ''syllogismos'' – "conclusion," "inference") or
logical appeal is a kind of
logical argument in which one
proposition (the conclusion) is
inferred from two others (the
premises) of a certain form, i.e.
categorical proposition.
In ''Prior Analytics,'' Aristotle defines syllogism as "a discourse in which, certain things having been supposed, something different from the things supposed results of necessity because these things are so." (24b18–20)
Despite this very general definition, he limits himself first to categorical syllogisms (and later to modal syllogisms). The syllogism was at the core of traditional deductive reasoning, where facts are determined by combining existing statements, in contrast to inductive reasoning where facts are determined by repeated observations. The syllogism was superseded by first-order predicate logic following the work of Gottlob Frege, in particular his ''Begriffsschrift'' (''Concept Script'') (1879).
Basic structure
A categorical syllogism consists of three parts: the major premise, the minor premise and the conclusion.
Each part is a categorical proposition, and each categorical proposition contains two categorical terms. In Aristotle, each of the premises is in the form "All A are B," "Some A are B", "No A are B" or "Some A are not B", where "A" is one term and "B" is another. "All A are B," and "No A are B" are termed ''universal'' propositions; "Some A are B" and "Some A are not B" are termed ''particular'' propositions. More modern logicians allow some variation. Each of the premises has one term in common with the conclusion: in a major premise, this is the ''major term'' (''i.e.,'' the predicate of the conclusion); in a minor premise, it is the ''minor term'' (the subject) of the conclusion. For example:
:Major premise: All men are mortal.
:Minor premise: All Greeks are men.
:Conclusion: All Greeks are mortal.
Each of the three distinct terms represents a category. In the above example, "men," "mortal," and "Greeks." "Mortal" is the major term; "Greeks", the minor term. The premises also have one term in common with each other, which is known as the ''middle term''; in this example, "man." Both of the premises are universal, as is the conclusion.
:Major premise: All mortals die.
:Minor premise: Some men are mortals.
:Conclusion: Some men die.
Here, the major term is "die", the minor term is "men," and the middle term is "mortals". The major premise is universal; the minor premise and the conclusion are particular.
A sorites is a form of argument in which a series of incomplete syllogisms is so arranged that the predicate of each premise forms the subject of the next until the subject of the first is joined with the predicate of the last in the conclusion. For example, if one argues that a given number of grains of sand does not make a heap and that an additional grain does not either, then to conclude that no additional amount of sand will make a heap is to construct a sorites argument.
Types of syllogism
Although there are infinitely many possible syllogisms, there are only a finite number of logically distinct types. We shall classify and enumerate them below. Note that the syllogism above has the abstract form:
:Major premise: All M are P.
:Minor premise: All S are M.
:Conclusion: All S are P.
(Note: M – Middle, S – subject, P – predicate. See below for more detailed explanation.)
The premises and conclusion of a syllogism can be any of four types, which are labeled by letters as follows. The meaning of the letters is given by the table:
{|
|-
|
| ''code''
|
| ''quantifier''
|
| ''subject''
|
| ''copula''
|
| ''predicate''
|
| ''type''
|
| ''example''
|-
|
| a
|
| All
|
| S
|
| are
|
| P
|
| universal affirmatives
|
| All humans are mortal.
|-
|
| e
|
| No
|
| S
|
| are
|
| P
|
| universal negatives
|
| No humans are perfect.
|-
|
| i
|
| Some
|
| S
|
| are
|
| P
|
| particular affirmatives
|
| Some humans are healthy.
|-
|
| o
|
| Some
|
| S
|
| are not
|
| P
|
| particular negatives
|
| Some humans are not clever.
|}
In Analytics, Aristotle mostly uses the letters A, B and C as term place holders, rather than giving concrete examples, an innovation at the time. It is traditional to use ''is'' rather than ''are'' as the copula, hence ''All A is B'' rather than ''All As are Bs''. It is traditional and convenient practice to use a, e, i, o as infix operators to enable the categorical statements to be written succinctly thus:
! Form
|
! Shorthand
|
All A is B
|
AaB
|
No A is B
|
AeB
|
Some A is B
|
AiB
|
Some A is not B
|
AoB
|
This particular syllogistic form is dubbed BARBARA (see below) and can be written neatly as BaC,AaB -> AaC.
The letter S is the subject of the conclusion, P is the predicate of the conclusion, and M is the middle term. The major premise links M with P and the minor premise links M with S. However, the middle term can be either the subject or the predicate of each premise where it appears. The differing positions of the major, minor, and middle terms gives rise to another classification of syllogisms known as the ''figure''. Given that in each case the conclusion is S-P, the four figures are:
{|
|
|
| ''Figure 1''
|
| ''Figure 2''
|
| ''Figure 3''
|
| ''Figure 4''
|-
| Major premise:
|
| M–P
|
| P–M
|
| M–P
|
| P–M
|-
| Minor premise:
|
| S–M
|
| S–M
|
| M–S
|
| M–S
|}
Putting it all together, there are 256 possible types of syllogisms (or 512 if the order of the major and minor premises is changed, although this makes no difference logically). Each premise and the conclusion can be of type A, E, I or O, and the syllogism can be any of the four figures. A syllogism can be described briefly by giving the letters for the premises and conclusion followed by the number for the figure. For example, the syllogism BARBARA above is AAA-1, or "A-A-A in the first figure".
The vast majority of the 256 possible forms of syllogism are invalid (the conclusion does not follow logically from the premises). The table below shows the valid forms. Even some of these are sometimes considered to commit the existential fallacy, meaning they are invalid if they mention an empty category. These controversial patterns are marked in ''italics''.
{|
|-
|''Figure 1''
|''Figure 2''
|''Figure 3''
|''Figure 4''
|-
|Barbara
|Cesare
|Datisi
|Calemes
|-
|Celarent
|Camestres
|Disamis
|Dimatis
|-
|Darii
|Festino
|Ferison
|Fresison
|-
|Ferio
|Baroco
|Bocardo
|''Calemos''
|-
|''Barbari''
|''Cesaro''
|''Felapton''
|''Fesapo''
|-
|''Celaront''
|''Camestros''
|''Darapti''
|''Bamalip''
|}
The letters A, E, I, O have been used since the medieval Schools to form mnemonic names for the forms as follows: 'Barbara' stands for AAA, 'Celarent' for EAE, etc.
Next to each premise and conclusion is a shorthand description of the sentence. So in AAI-3, the premise "All squares are rectangles" becomes "MaP"; the symbols mean that the first term ("square") is the middle term, the second term ("rectangle") is the predicate of the conclusion, and the relationship between the two terms is labeled "a" (All M are P).
The following table shows all syllogisms that are essentially different. The similar syllogisms share actually the same premises, just written in a different way. For example "Some pets are kittens" (SiM in Darii) could also be written as "Some kittens are pets" (MiS is Datisi).
In the Venn diagrams the black areas tell, that there are no elements, and the red areas tell, that there is at least one element.
Examples
Barbara (AAA-1)
: All men are mortal. (MaP)
: All Greeks are men. (SaM)
:
∴ All Greeks are mortal. (SaP)
Celarent (EAE-1)
Similar: Cesare (EAE-2)
: No reptiles have fur. (MeP)
: All snakes are reptiles. (SaM)
:∴ No snakes have fur. (SeP)
Darii (AII-1)
Similar: Datisi (AII-3)
: All rabbits have fur. (MaP)
: Some pets are rabbits. (SiM)
:∴ Some pets have fur. (SiP)
Ferio (EIO-1)
Similar: Festino (EIO-2), Ferison (EIO-3), Fresison (EIO-4)
: No homework is fun. (MeP)
: Some reading is homework. (SiM)
:∴ Some reading is not fun. (SoP)
Baroco (AOO-2)
: All informative things are useful. (PaM)
: Some websites are not useful. (SoM)
:∴ Some websites are not informative. (SoP)
Bocardo (OAO-3)
: Some cats have no tails. (MoP)
: All cats are mammals. (MaS)
:∴ Some mammals have no tails. (SoP)
----
''Barbari (AAI-1)''
: All men are mortal. (MaP)
: All Greeks are men. (SaM)
:∴ Some Greeks are mortal. (SiP)
''Celaront (EAO-1)''
Similar: ''Cesaro (EAO-2)''
: No reptiles have fur. (MeP)
: All snakes are reptiles. (SaM)
:∴ Some snakes have no fur. (SoP)
''Camestros (AEO-2)''
Similar: ''Calemos (AEO-4)''
: All horses have hooves. (PaM)
: No humans have hooves. (SeM)
:∴ Some humans are not horses. (SoP)
''Felapton (EAO-3)''
Similar: ''Fesapo (EAO-4)''
: No flowers are animals. (MeP)
: All flowers are plants. (MaS)
:∴ Some plants are not animals. (SoP)
''Darapti (AAI-3)''
: All
squares are
rectangles. (MaP)
: All squares are
rhombs. (MaS)
:∴ Some rhombs are rectangles. (SiP)
Table of all syllogisms
This table shows all 24 valid syllogisms, represented by
Venn diagrams.
(9 of them, on the right side of the table, require that one category must not be empty.)
Syllogisms of the same type are in the same row, and very similar syllogisms are in the same column.
1
|
[[File:Modus Barbara.svg |
[[File:Modus Celarent.svg |
|
[[File:Modus Darii.svg |
|
[[File:Modus Ferio.svg |
|
|
[[File:Modus Barbari.svg |
[[File:Modus Celaront.svg |
|
|
|
|
2
|
|
[[File:Modus Cesare.svg |
[[File:Modus Camestres.svg |
|
|
[[File:Modus Festino.svg |
[[File:Modus Baroco.svg |
|
|
[[File:Modus Cesaro.svg |
[[File:Modus Camestros.svg |
|
|
|
3
|
|
|
|
[[File:Modus Datisi.svg |
[[File:Modus Disamis.svg |
[[File:Modus Ferison.svg |
|
[[File:Modus Bocardo.svg |
|
|
|
[[File:Modus Felapton.svg |
[[File:Modus Darapti.svg |
|
4
|
|
|
[[File:Modus Calemes.svg |
|
[[File:Modus Dimatis.svg |
[[File:Modus Fresison.svg |
|
|
|
|
[[File:Modus Calemos.svg |
[[File:Modus Fesapo.svg |
|
[[File:Modus Bamalip.svg |
Terms in syllogism
We may, with Aristotle, distinguish
singular terms such as ''Socrates'' and
general terms such as ''Greeks''. Aristotle further distinguished (a) terms that could be the subject of predication, and (b) terms that could be predicated of others by the use of the copula (is are). (Such a predication is known as a distributive as opposed to non-distributive as in ''Greeks are numerous''. It is clear that Aristotle's syllogism works only for distributive predication for we cannot reason ''All Greeks are animals, animals are numerous, therefore All Greeks are numerous''.) In Aristotle’s view singular terms were of type (a) and general terms of type (b). Thus ''Men'' can be predicated of ''Socrates'' but ''Socrates'' cannot be predicated of anything. Therefore to enable a term to be interchangeable — that is to be either in the subject or predicate position of a proposition in a syllogism — the terms must be general terms, or categorical terms as they came to be called. Consequently the propositions of a syllogism should be categorical propositions (both terms general) and syllogism employing just categorical terms came to be called categorical syllogisms.
It is clear that nothing would prevent a singular term occurring in a syllogism — so long as it was always in the subject position — however such a syllogism, even if valid, would not be a categorical syllogism. An example of such would be ''Socrates is a man, All men are mortal, therefore Socrates is mortal.'' Intuitively this is as valid as ''All Greeks are men, all men are mortal therefore all Greeks are mortals''. To argue that its validity can be explained by the theory of syllogism it would be necessary to show that ''Socrates is a man'' is the equivalent of a categorical proposition. It can be argued ''Socrates is a man'' is equivalent to ''All that are identical to Socrates are men'', so our non-categorical syllogism can be justified by use of the equivalence above and then citing BARBARA.
Existential import
If a statement includes a term so that the statement is false if the term has no instances (is not instantiated) then the statement is said to entail existential import with respect to that term. In particular, a universal statement of the form ''All A is B'' has existential import with respect to A if ''All A is B'' is false if there are no As.
The following problems arise:
: (a) In natural language and normal use, which statements of the forms All A is B, No A is B, Some A is B and Some A is not B have existential import and with respect to which terms?
: (b) In the four forms of categorical statements used in syllogism, which statements of the form AaB, AeB, AiB and AoB have existential import and with respect to which terms?
: (c) What existential imports must the forms AaB, AeB, AiB and AoB have for the square of opposition be valid?
: (d) What existential imports must the forms AaB, AeB, AiB and AoB to preserve the validity of the traditionally valid forms of syllogisms?
: (e) Are the existential imports required to satisfy (d) above such that the normal uses in natural languages of the forms All A is B, No A is B, Some A is B and Some A is not B are intuitively and fairly reflected by the categorical statements of forms Ahab, Abe, Ail and Alb?
For example, if it is accepted that AiB is false if there are no As and AaB entails AiB, then AiB has existential import with respect to A, and so does AaB. Further, if it is accepted that AiB entails BiA, then AiB and AaB have existential import with respect to B as well. Similarly, if AoB is false if there are no As, and AeB entails AoB, and AeB entails BeA (which in turn entails BoA) then both AeB and AoB have existential import with respect to both A and B. It follows immediately that all universal categorical statements have existential import with respect to both terms. If AaB and AeB is a fair representation of the use of statements in normal natural language of All A is B and No A is B respectively, then the following example consequences arise:
:"All flying horses are mythological" is false if there are not flying horses.
:If "No men are fire-eating rabbits" is true, then "There are fire-eating dragons" is false.
and so on.
If it is ruled that no universal statement has existential import then the square of opposition fails in several respects (e.g. AaB does not entail AiB) and a number of syllogisms are no longer valid (e.g. BaC,AaB->AiC).
These problems and paradoxes arise in both natural language statements and statements in syllogism form because of ambiguity, in particular ambiguity with respect to All. If "Fred claims all his books were Pulitzer Prize winners", is Fred claiming that he wrote any books? If not, then is what he claims true? Suppose Jane says none of her friends are poor; is that true if she has no friends? The first-order predicate calculus avoids the problems of such ambiguity by using formulae that carry no existential import with respect to universal statements; existential claims have to be explicitly stated. Thus natural language statements of the forms All A is B, No A is B, Some A is B and Some A is not B can be exactly represented in first order predicate calculus in which any existential import with respect to terms A and/or B is made explicitly or not made at all. Consequently the four forms AaB, AeB, AiB and AoB can be represented in first order predicate in every combination of existential import, so that it can establish which construal, if any, preserves the square of opposition and the validly of the traditionally valid syllogism. Strawson claims that such a construal is possible, but the results are such that, in his view, the answer to question (a) above is ''no''.
Syllogism in the history of logic
Syllogism dominated Western philosophical thought until the 17th Century. At that time, Sir Francis Bacon rejected the idea of syllogism and deductive reasoning by asserting that it was fallible and illogical. Bacon offered a more inductive approach to logic in which experiments were conducted and axioms were drawn from the observations discovered in them.
In the 19th Century, modifications to syllogism were incorporated to deal with disjunctive ("A or B") and conditional ("if A then B") statements. Kant famously claimed, in ''Logic'' (1800), that logic was the one completed science, and that Aristotelian logic more or less included everything about logic there was to know. Though it should be kept in mind that this work is not necessarily representative of Kant's mature philosophy, and that this philosophy is generally regarded as an innovation to logic itself. Though there were alternative systems of logic such as Avicennian logic or Indian logic elsewhere, Kant's opinion stood unchallenged in the West until 1879 when Frege published his ''Begriffsschrift'' (''Concept Script''). This introduced a calculus, a method of representing categorical statements — and statements that are not provided for in syllogism as well — by the use of quantifiers and variables.
This led to the rapid development of sentential logic and first-order predicate logic, subsuming syllogistic reasoning, which was, therefore, after 2000 years, suddenly considered obsolete by many. The Aristotelian system is explicated in modern fora of academia primarily in introductory material and historical study.
One notable exception to this modern relegation, however, is the continued application of the intricate rules of Aristotelian logic, as taught by St. Thomas Aquinas, in the Roman Curia's Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, and the Apostolic Tribunal of the Roman Rota.
Syllogistic Fallacies
People often make mistakes when reasoning syllogistically.
For instance, from the premises some A are B, some B are C, people tend to come to a definitive conclusion that therefore some A are C. However, this does not follow according to the rules of classical logic. For instance, while some cats (A) are black (B), and some black things (B) are televisions (C), it does not follow from the parameters that some cats (A) are televisions (C). This is because first, the mood of the syllogism invoked is illicit (III), and second, the supposition of the middle term is variable between that of the middle term in the major premise, and that of the middle term in the minor premise (not all "some" cats are by necessity of logic the same "some black things").
Determining the validity of a syllogism involves determining the distribution of each term in each statement, meaning whether all members of that term are accounted for.
In simple syllogistic patterns, the fallacies of invalid patterns are:
Undistributed middle: Neither of the premises accounts for all members of the middle term, which consequently fails to link the major and minor term.
Illicit treatment of the major term: The conclusion implicates all members of the major term (P — meaning the proposition is negative); however, the major premise does not account for them all (i.e., P is either an affirmative predicate or a particular subject there).
Illicit treatment of the minor term: Same as above, but for the minor term (S — meaning the proposition is universal) and minor premise (where S is either a particular subject or an affirmative predicate).
Exclusive premises: Both premises are negative, meaning no link is established between the major and minor terms.
Affirmative conclusion from a negative premise: If either premise is negative, the conclusion must also be.
Negative conclusion from affirmative premises: If both premises are affirmative, the conclusion must also be.
Existential fallacy: This is a more controversial one. If both premises are universal, i.e. "All" or "No" statements, one school of thought says they do not imply the existence of any members of the terms. In this case, the conclusion cannot be existential; i.e. beginning with "Some". Another school of thought says that affirmative statements (universal or particular) do imply the subject's existence, but negatives do not. A third school of thought says that the any type of proposition may or may not involve the subject's existence, and although this may condition the conclusion it does not affect the form of the syllogism.
See also
Enthymeme
Forms of syllogism:
* Disjunctive syllogism
* Hypothetical syllogism
* Polysyllogism
* Prosleptic syllogism
* Quasi-syllogism
* Statistical syllogism
Syllogistic fallacy
The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures
Venn diagram
Notes
References
Aristotle, ''Prior Analytics''. transl. Robin Smith (Hackett, 1989) ISBN 0-87220-064-7
Blackburn, Simon, 1996. "Syllogism" in the ''Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy''. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-283134-8.
Broadie, Alexander, 1993. ''Introduction to Medieval Logic''. Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-824026-0.
Irving Copi, 1969. ''Introduction to Logic'', 3rd ed. Macmillan Company.
John Corcoran (logician), 1972. ''Completeness of an ancient logic'' Journal of Symbolic Logic 37: 696–702.
John Corcoran (logician), 1994. ''The founding of logic. Modern interpretations of Aristotle's logic'' Ancient Philosophy 14: 9–24.
Hamblin, Charles L., 1970. ''Fallacies'', Methuen : London, ISBN 0-416-70070-5. Cf. on validity of syllogisms: "A simple set of rules of validity was finally produced in the later Middle Ages, based on the concept of Distribution.“
Jan Łukasiewicz, 1987 (1957). ''Aristotle's Syllogistic from the Standpoint of Modern Formal Logic''. New York: Garland Publishers. ISBN 0824069242. OCLC 15015545.
Smiley Timothy, 1973. "What is a syllogism?," Journal of Philosophical Logic 2: 136–154.
Smith Robin, 1986. "Immediate propositions and Aristotle's proof theory," Ancient Philosophy 6: 47–68.
External links
Aristotle's Prior Analytics: the Theory of Categorical Syllogism an annotated bibliography on Aristotle's syllogistic
Abbreviatio Montana article by Prof. R. J. Kilcullen of Macquarie University on the medieval classification of syllogisms.
The Figures of the Syllogism is a brief table listing the forms of the syllogism.
Interactive Syllogistic Machine A web based syllogistic machine for exploring fallacies, figures, and modes of syllogisms.
www.fibonicci.co.uk/syllogisms some fun syllogism tests/quizzes
Syllogistic Reasoning in Buddhism – Example & Worksheet
Category:Traditional logic
Category:Greek loanwords
Category:Arguments
bg:Силогизъм
ca:Sil·logisme
cs:Sylogismus
da:Syllogisme
de:Syllogismus
et:Süllogism
es:Silogismo
fa:قیاس (منطق)
fr:Syllogisme
ko:삼단논법
hi:न्यायवाक्य
io:Silogismo
ia:Syllogismo
is:Rökhenda
it:Sillogismo
he:סילוגיזם
lb:Syllogismus
hu:Szillogizmus
nl:Syllogisme
ja:三段論法
no:Syllogisme
nov:Silogisme
pl:Sylogizm
pt:Silogismo
ro:Silogism
ru:Категорический силлогизм
simple:Syllogism
sk:Kategorický sylogizmus
sl:Silogizem
sr:Силогизам
sv:Syllogism
tl:Silogismo
vi:Tam đoạn luận
zh-yue:定言三段論
zh:直言三段论