|
This article needs attention from an expert on the subject. Please add a reason or a talk parameter to this template to explain the issue with the article. WikiProject Logic may be able to help recruit an expert. (January 2011) |
Saul Aaron Kripke (born November 13, 1940) is an American philosopher and logician. He is a professor emeritus at Princeton and teaches as a Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the CUNY Graduate Center. Since the 1960s Kripke has been a central figure in a number of fields related to mathematical logic, philosophy of language, philosophy of mathematics, metaphysics, epistemology, and set theory. Much of his work remains unpublished or exists only as tape-recordings and privately circulated manuscripts. Kripke was the recipient of the 2001 Schock Prize in Logic and Philosophy. A recent poll conducted among philosophers ranked Kripke among the top ten most important philosophers of the past 200 years.[1]
Kripke has made influential and original contributions to logic, especially modal logic, since he was a teenager. Unusual for a professional philosopher, his only degree is an undergraduate degree from Harvard, in mathematics. His work has profoundly influenced analytic philosophy, with his principal contribution being a semantics for modal logic, involving possible worlds as described in a system now called Kripke semantics.[2] Another of his most important contributions is his argument that necessity is a 'metaphysical' notion, which should be separated from the epistemic notion of a priori, and that there are necessary a posteriori truths, such as "Water is H2O." He has also contributed an original reading of Wittgenstein, referred to as "Kripkenstein." His most famous work is Naming and Necessity (1980).
Saul Kripke is the oldest of three children born to Dorothy K. Kripke and Rabbi Myer S. Kripke.[3] His father was the leader of Beth El Synagogue, the only Conservative congregation in Omaha, Nebraska, while his mother wrote educational Jewish books for children. Saul and his two sisters, Madeline and Netta, attended Dundee Grade School and Omaha Central High School. Kripke was labelled a prodigy, having taught himself Ancient Hebrew by the age of six, read the complete works of Shakespeare by nine, and mastered the works of Descartes and complex mathematical problems before graduating elementary school.[4][5] He wrote his first completeness theorem in modal logic at the age of 17, and had it published a year later. After graduating from high school in 1958, Kripke attended Harvard University and graduated summa cum laude obtaining a bachelor's degree in mathematics. During his sophomore year at Harvard, Kripke taught a graduate-level logic course at nearby MIT. Upon graduation (1962) he received a Fulbright Fellowship, and in 1963 was appointed to the Society of Fellows.
After teaching briefly at Harvard, he moved to Rockefeller University in New York City in 1967, and then received a full-time position at Princeton University in 1977. In 1988 he received the university's Behrman Award for distinguished achievement in the humanities. In 2002 Kripke began teaching at the CUNY Graduate Center in midtown Manhattan, and was appointed a distinguished professor of philosophy there in 2003. He was married to philosopher Margaret Gilbert.
He has received honorary degrees from the University of Nebraska, Omaha (1977), Johns Hopkins University (1997), University of Haifa, Israel (1998), and the University of Pennsylvania (2005). He is a member of the American Philosophical Society, an elected Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences and a Corresponding Fellow of the British Academy. He won the Schock Prize in Logic and Philosophy in 2001.
He is uncle of the notable television writer, director, and producer Eric Kripke.
Kripke models for modal logic systems
Kripke's contributions to philosophy include:
- Kripke semantics for modal and related logics, published in several essays beginning while he was still in his teens.
- His 1970 Princeton lectures Naming and Necessity (published in 1972 and 1980), that significantly restructured philosophy of language.
- His interpretation of Wittgenstein.
- His theory of truth.
He has also contributed to set-theory (see admissible ordinal and Kripke-Platek set theory)
Two of Kripke's earlier works, A Completeness Theorem in Modal Logic and Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic, the former written while he was still a teenager, were on the subject of modal logic. The most familiar logics in the modal family are constructed from a weak logic called K, named after Kripke for his contributions to modal logic. Kripke introduced the now-standard Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics) for modal logics. Kripke semantics is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems. It was first made for modal logics, and later adapted to intuitionistic logic and other non-classical systems. The discovery of Kripke semantics was a breakthrough in the making of non-classical logics, because the model theory of such logics was absent prior to Kripke.
A Kripke frame or modal frame is a pair Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,R\rangle , where W is a non-empty set, and R is a binary relation on W. Elements of W are called nodes or worlds, and R is known as the accessibility relation. Depending on the properties of the accessibility relation (transitivity, reflexivity, etc.), the corresponding frame is described, by extension, as being transitive, reflexive, etc.
A Kripke model is a triple Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,R,\Vdash\rangle , where Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,R\rangle
is a Kripke frame, and Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \Vdash
is a relation between nodes of W and modal formulas, such that:
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash\neg A
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\nVdash A
,
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A\to B
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\nVdash A
or Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash B
,
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash\Box A
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \forall u\,(w\; R\; u \to u\Vdash A)
.
We read Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A
as “w satisfies A”, “A is satisfied in w”, or “w forces A”. The relation Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \Vdash
is called the satisfaction relation, evaluation, or forcing relation. The satisfaction relation is uniquely determined by its value on propositional variables.
A formula A is valid in:
- a model Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,R,\Vdash\rangle
, if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A
for all w ∈ W,
- a frame Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,R\rangle
, if it is valid in Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,R,\Vdash\rangle
for all possible choices of Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \Vdash
,
- a class C of frames or models, if it is valid in every member of C.
We define Thm(C) to be the set of all formulas that are valid in C. Conversely, if X is a set of formulas, let Mod(X) be the class of all frames which validate every formula from X.
A modal logic (i.e., a set of formulas) L is sound with respect to a class of frames C, if L ⊆ Thm(C). L is complete with respect to C if L ⊇ Thm(C).
Semantics is useful for investigating a logic (i.e. a derivation system) only if the semantical entailment relation reflects its syntactical counterpart, the consequence relation (derivability). It is vital to know which modal logics are sound and complete with respect to a class of Kripke frames, and for them, to determine which class it is.
For any class C of Kripke frames, Thm(C) is a normal modal logic (in particular, theorems of the minimal normal modal logic, K, are valid in every Kripke model). However, the converse does not hold generally. There are Kripke incomplete normal modal logics, which is unproblematic, because most of the modal systems studied are complete of classes of frames described by simple conditions.
A normal modal logic L corresponds to a class of frames C, if C = Mod(L). In other words, C is the largest class of frames such that L is sound wrt C. It follows that L is Kripke complete if and only if it is complete of its corresponding class.
Consider the schema T : Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \Box A\to A . T is valid in any reflexive frame Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,R\rangle
- if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash \Box A
, then Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A
since w R w. On the other hand, a frame which validates T has to be reflexive: fix w ∈ W, and define satisfaction of a propositional variable p as follows: Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): u\Vdash p
if and only if w R u. Then Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash \Box p
, thus Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash p
by T, which means w R w using the definition of Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \Vdash
. T corresponds to the class of reflexive Kripke frames.
It is often much easier to characterize the corresponding class of L than to prove its completeness, thus correspondence serves as a guide to completeness proofs. Correspondence is also used to show incompleteness of modal logics: suppose L1 ⊆ L2 are normal modal logics that correspond to the same class of frames, but L1 does not prove all theorems of L2. Then L1 is Kripke incomplete. For example, the schema Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \Box(A\equiv\Box A)\to\Box A
generates an incomplete logic, as it corresponds to the same class of frames as GL (viz. transitive and converse well-founded frames), but does not prove the GL-tautology Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \Box A\to\Box\Box A
.
For any normal modal logic L, a Kripke model (called the canonical model) can be constructed, which validates precisely the theorems of L, by an adaptation of the standard technique of using maximal consistent sets as models. Canonical Kripke models play a role similar to the Lindenbaum–Tarski algebra construction in algebraic semantics.
A set of formulas is L-consistent if no contradiction can be derived from them using the axioms of L, and Modus Ponens. A maximal L-consistent set (an L-MCS for short) is an L-consistent set which has no proper L-consistent superset.
The canonical model of L is a Kripke model Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,R,\Vdash\rangle , where W is the set of all L-MCS, and the relations R and Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \Vdash
are as follows:
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): X\;R\;Y
if and only if for every formula Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): A
, if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \Box A\in X
then Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): A\in Y
,
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): X\Vdash A
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): A\in X
.
The canonical model is a model of L, as every L-MCS contains all theorems of L. By Zorn's lemma, each L-consistent set is contained in an L-MCS, in particular every formula unprovable in L has a counterexample in the canonical model.
The main application of canonical models are completeness proofs. Properties of the canonical model of K immediately imply completeness of K with respect to the class of all Kripke frames. This argument does not work for arbitrary L, because there is no guarantee that the underlying frame of the canonical model satisfies the frame conditions of L.
We say that a formula or a set X of formulas is canonical with respect to a property P of Kripke frames, if
- X is valid in every frame which satisfies P,
- for any normal modal logic L which contains X, the underlying frame of the canonical model of L satisfies P.
A union of canonical sets of formulas is itself canonical. It follows from the preceding discussion that any logic axiomatized by a canonical set of formulas is Kripke complete, and compact.
The axioms T, 4, D, B, 5, H, G (and thus any combination of them) are canonical. GL and Grz are not canonical, because they are not compact. The axiom M by itself is not canonical (Goldblatt, 1991), but the combined logic S4.1 (in fact, even K4.1) is canonical.
In general, it is undecidable whether a given axiom is canonical. We know a nice sufficient condition: H. Sahlqvist identified a broad class of formulas (now called Sahlqvist formulas) such that:
- a Sahlqvist formula is canonical,
- the class of frames corresponding to a Sahlqvist formula is first-order definable,
- there is an algorithm which computes the corresponding frame condition to a given Sahlqvist formula.
This is a powerful criterion: for example, all axioms listed above as canonical are (equivalent to) Sahlqvist formulas. A logic has the finite model property (FMP) if it is complete with respect to a class of finite frames. An application of this notion is the decidability question: it follows from Post's theorem that a recursively axiomatized modal logic L which has FMP is decidable, provided it is decidable whether a given finite frame is a model of L. In particular, every finitely axiomatizable logic with FMP is decidable.
There are various methods for establishing FMP for a given logic. Refinements and extensions of the canonical model construction often work, using tools such as filtration or unravelling. As another possibility, completeness proofs based on cut-free sequent calculi usually produce finite models directly.
Most of the modal systems used in practice (including all listed above) have FMP.
In some cases, we can use FMP to prove Kripke completeness of a logic: every normal modal logic is complete wrt a class of modal algebras, and a finite modal algebra can be transformed into a Kripke frame. As an example, Robert Bull proved using this method that every normal extension of S4.3 has FMP, and is Kripke complete.
Kripke semantics has a straightforward generalization to logics with more than one modality. A Kripke frame for a language with Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \{\Box_i\mid\,i\in I\}
as the set of its necessity operators consists of a non-empty set W equipped with binary relations Ri for each i ∈ I. The definition of a satisfaction relation is modified as follows:
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash\Box_i A
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \forall u\,(w\;R_i\;u\Rightarrow u\Vdash A).
A simplified semantics, discovered by Tim Carlson, is often used for polymodal provability logics. A Carlson model is a structure Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,R,\{D_i\}_{i\in I},\Vdash\rangle
with a single accessibility relation R, and subsets Di ⊆ W for each modality. Satisfaction is defined as:
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash\Box_i A
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \forall u\in D_i\,(w\;R\;u\Rightarrow u\Vdash A).
Carlson models are easier to visualize and to work with than usual polymodal Kripke models; there are, however, Kripke complete polymodal logics which are Carlson incomplete.
In "Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic", published in 1963, Kripke responded to a difficulty with classical quantification theory. The motivation for the world-relative approach was to represent the possibility that objects in one world may fail to exist in another. If standard quantifier rules are used, however, every term must refer to something that exists in all the possible worlds. This seems incompatible with our ordinary practice of using terms to refer to things that exist contingently.
Kripke's response to this difficulty was to eliminate terms. He gave an example of a system that uses the world-relative interpretation and preserves the classical rules. However, the costs are severe. First, his language is artificially impoverished, and second, the rules for the propositional modal logic must be weakened.
Kripke's possible worlds theory has been used by narratologists (beginning with Pavel and Dolezel) to understand "reader's manipulation of alternative plot developments, or the characters' planned or fantasized alternative action series," has become especially useful in the analysis of hyperfiction.[6]
Kripke semantics for the intuitionistic logic follows the same principles as the semantics of modal logic, but uses a different definition of satisfaction.
An intuitionistic Kripke model is a triple Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,\le,\Vdash\rangle , where Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,\le\rangle
is a partially ordered Kripke frame, and Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \Vdash
satisfies the following conditions:
- if p is a propositional variable, Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\le u
, and Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash p , then Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): u\Vdash p
(persistency condition),
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A\land B
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A
and Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash B
,
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A\lor B
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A
or Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash B
,
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A\to B
if and only if for all Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): u\ge w
, Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): u\Vdash A
implies Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): u\Vdash B
,
- not Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash\bot
.
Intuitionistic logic is sound and complete with respect to its Kripke semantics, and it has the Finite Model Property.
Intuitionistic first-order logic
Let L be a first-order language. A Kripke model of L is a triple Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,\le,\{M_w\}_{w\in W}\rangle , where Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \langle W,\le\rangle
is an intuitionistic Kripke frame, Mw is a
(classical) L-structure for each node w ∈ W, and the following compatibility conditions hold whenever u ≤ v:
- the domain of Mu is included in the domain of Mv,
- realizations of function symbols in Mu and Mv agree on elements of Mu,
- for each n-ary predicate P and elements a1,…,an ∈ Mu: if P(a1,…,an) holds in Mu, then it holds in Mv.
Given an evaluation e of variables by elements of Mw, we define the satisfaction relation Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A[e]
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash P(t_1,\dots,t_n)[e]
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): P(t_1[e],\dots,t_n[e])
holds in Mw,
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash(A\land B)[e]
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A[e]
and Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash B[e]
,
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash(A\lor B)[e]
if and only if Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A[e]
or Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash B[e]
,
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash(A\to B)[e]
if and only if for all Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): u\ge w
, Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): u\Vdash A[e]
implies Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): u\Vdash B[e]
,
- not Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash\bot[e]
,
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash(\exists x\,A)[e]
if and only if there exists an Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): a\in M_w
such that Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash A[e(x\to a)]
,
- Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): w\Vdash(\forall x\,A)[e]
if and only if for every Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): u\ge w
and every Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): a\in M_u
, Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): u\Vdash A[e(x\to a)] . Here e(x→a) is the evaluation which gives x the value a, and otherwise agrees with e.
[edit] Naming and Necessity
The three lectures that form Naming and Necessity constitute an attack on descriptivist theory of names. Kripke attributes variants of descriptivist theories to Frege, Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein and John Searle, among others. According to descriptivist theories, proper names either are synonymous with descriptions, or have their reference determined by virtue of the name's being associated with a description or cluster of descriptions that an object uniquely satisfies. Kripke rejects both these kinds of descriptivism. He gives several examples purporting to render descriptivism implausible as a theory of how names get their references determined (e.g., surely Aristotle could have died at age two and so not satisfied any of the descriptions we associate with his name, and yet it would seem wrong to deny that he was Aristotle).
As an alternative, Kripke outlined a causal theory of reference, according to which a name refers to an object by virtue of a causal connection with the object as mediated through communities of speakers. He points out that proper names, in contrast to most descriptions, are rigid designators. That is, a proper name refers to the named object in every possible world in which the object exists, while most descriptions designate different objects in different possible worlds. For example, 'Nixon' refers to the same person in every possible world in which Nixon exists, while 'the person who won the United States presidential election of 1968' could refer to Nixon, Humphrey, or others in different possible worlds.
Kripke also raised the prospect of a posteriori necessities[disambiguation needed ] — facts that are necessarily true, though they can be known only through empirical investigation. Examples include “Hesperus is Phosphorus”, “Cicero is Tully”, “Water is H2O” and other identity claims where two names refer to the same object.
Finally, Kripke gave an argument against identity materialism in the philosophy of mind, the view that every mental fact is identical with some physical fact. Kripke argued that the only way to defend this identity is as an a posteriori necessary identity, but that such an identity — e.g., pain is C-fibers firing — could not be necessary, given the possibility of pain that has nothing to do with C-fibers firing. Similar arguments have been proposed by David Chalmers.[7]
Kripke delivered the John Locke lectures in philosophy at Oxford in 1973. Titled Reference and Existence, they are in many respects a continuation of Naming and Necessity, and deal with the subjects of fictional names and perceptual error. They have never been published and the transcript is officially available only in a reading copy in the university philosophy library, which cannot be copied or cited without Kripke's permission.
In a 1995 paper, philosopher Quentin Smith argued that key concepts in Kripke's new theory of reference had originated from the work of Ruth Barcan Marcus more than a decade earlier.[8] Smith identified six significant ideas to the New Theory that he claimed Marcus had developed: (1) The idea that proper names are direct references, which don't consist of contained definitions. (2) While one can single out a single thing by a description, this description is not equivalent with a proper name of this thing. (3) The modal argument that proper names are directly referential, and not disguised descriptions. (4) A formal modal logic proof of the necessity of identity. (5) The concept of a rigid designator, though the actual name of the concept was coined by Kripke.(6) The idea of a posteriori identity. Smith proceeded to argue that Kripke failed to understand Marcus' theory at the time, yet later adopted many of its key conceptual themes in his New Theory of Reference.
Other scholars have subsequently offered detailed responses arguing that no plagiarism occurred.[9]
Kripke’s main propositions in Naming and Necessity concerning proper names are that the meaning of a name simply is the object it refers to and that a name’s referent is determined by a causal link between some sort of “baptism” and the utterance of the name. Nevertheless he acknowledges the possibility that propositions containing names may have some additional semantic properties,[10] properties that could explain why two names referring to the same person may give different truth values in propositions about beliefs. For example, Lois Lane believes that Superman can fly, although she does not believe that Clark Kent can fly. This can be accounted for if the names “Superman” and “Clark Kent”, though referring to the same person, have distinct semantic properties.
In the article “A Puzzle about Belief” Kripke seems to oppose even this possibility. His argument can be reconstructed in the following way: The idea that two names referring to the same object may have different semantic properties is supposed to explain that coreferring names behave differently in propositions about beliefs (as in Lois Lane's case). But the same phenomenon occurs even with coreferring names that obviously have the same semantic properties:
Kripke invites us to imagine a French, monolingual boy, Pierre, who believes the following: “Londres est joli.” (“London is beautiful.”) Pierre moves to London without realizing that London = Londres. He then learns English the same way a child would learn the language, that is, not by translating words from French to English. Pierre learns the name “London” from the unattractive part of the city in which he lives, so he comes to believe that London is not beautiful. If Kripke’s account is correct, Pierre now believes both that "Londres" is "joli" and that "London" is not beautiful. This cannot be explained by coreferring names having different semantic properties. According to Kripke, this demonstrates that attributing additional semantic properties to names does not explain what it is intended to prove.
First published in 1982, Kripke's Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language contends that the central argument of Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations centers on a devastating rule-following paradox that undermines the possibility of our ever following rules in our use of language. Kripke writes that this paradox is "the most radical and original skeptical problem that philosophy has seen to date." (p. 60) Kripke argues that Wittgenstein does not reject the argument that leads to the rule-following paradox, but accepts it and offers a 'skeptical solution' to ameliorate the paradox's destructive effects.
Whilst most commentators[citation needed] accept that the Philosophical Investigations contains the rule-following paradox as Kripke presents it, few have concurred with Kripke when he attributes a skeptical solution to Wittgenstein. It should be noted that Kripke himself expresses doubts in Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language as to whether Wittgenstein would endorse his interpretation of the Philosophical Investigations. He says that the work should not be read as an attempt to give an accurate statement of Wittgenstein's views, but rather as an account of Wittgenstein's argument "as it struck Kripke, as it presented a problem for him" (p. 5).
The portmanteau "Kripkenstein" has been coined as a jesting nickname for Kripke's reading of the Philosophical Investigations. The real significance of "Kripkenstein" was to put forward a clear statement of a new kind of skepticism, dubbed "meaning skepticism", which is the idea that for an isolated individual there is no fact in virtue of which he/she means one thing rather than another by the use of a word. Kripke's "skeptical solution" to meaning skepticism is to ground meaning in the behavior of a community.
Kripke's book generated a large secondary literature,[citation needed] divided between those who find his skeptical problem interesting and perceptive, and others, such as Gordon Baker and Peter Hacker, who argue that his meaning skepticism is a pseudo-problem that stems from a confused, selective reading of Wittgenstein. Kripke's position has, however recently been defended against these and other attacks by the Cambridge philosopher Martin Kusch (2006), and Wittgenstein scholar David G. Stern considers the book to be "the most influential and widely discussed" work on Wittgenstein since the 1980s.[11]
|
This section only describes one highly specialized aspect of its associated subject. Please help improve this article by adding more general information. The talk page may contain suggestions. (October 2009) |
In his 1975 article "Outline of a Theory of Truth", Kripke showed that a language can consistently contain its own truth predicate, which was deemed impossible by Alfred Tarski, a pioneer in the area of formal theories of truth. The approach involves letting truth be a partially defined property over the set of grammatically well-formed sentences in the language. Kripke showed how to do this recursively by starting from the set of expressions in a language which do not contain the truth predicate, and defining a truth predicate over just that segment: this action adds new sentences to the language, and truth is in turn defined for all of them. Unlike Tarski's approach, however, Kripke's lets "truth" be the union of all of these definition-stages; after a denumerable infinity of steps the language reaches a "fixed point" such that using Kripke's method to expand the truth-predicate does not change the language any further. Such a fixed point can then be taken as the basic form of a natural language containing its own truth predicate. But this predicate is undefined for any sentences that do not, so to speak, "bottom out" in simpler sentences not containing a truth predicate. That is, " 'Snow is white' is true" is well-defined, as is " ' "Snow is white" is true' is true," and so forth, but neither "This sentence is true" nor "This sentence is not true" receive truth-conditions; they are, in Kripke's terms, "ungrounded."
Kripke is an observant Jew.[12] Discussing how his religious views influenced his philosophical views (in an interview with Andreas Saugstad) he stated: "I don't have the prejudices many have today, I don't believe in a naturalist world view. I don't base my thinking on prejudices or a world view and do not believe in materialism."[13]
- Fulbright Scholar (1962–1963)
- Society of Fellows, Harvard University (1963–1966).
- Doctor of Humane Letters, honorary degree, University of Nebraska, 1977.
- Fellow, American Academy of Arts and Sciences (1978–).
- Corresponding Fellow, British Academy (1985–).
- Howard Behrman Award, Princeton University, 1988.
- Fellow, Academia Scientiarum et Artium Europaea (1993–).
- Doctor of Humane Letters, honorary degree, Johns Hopkins University, 1997.
- Doctor of Humane Letters, honorary degree, University of Haifa, Israel, 1998.
- Fellow, Norwegian Academy of Sciences (2000–).
- Schock Prize in Logic and Philosophy, Swedish Academy of Sciences, 2001.
- Doctor of Humane Letters, honorary degree, University of Pennsylvania, 2005.
- Fellow, American Philosophical Society (2005–).
- 1959. "A Completeness Theorem in Modal Logic", Journal of Symbolic Logic 24(1):1–14.
- 1959. "Distinguished Constituents" (abstract), The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 24(4):323.
- 1959. "Semantical Analysis of Modal Logic" (abstract), The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 24(4):323-324.
- 1959. "The Problem of Entailment" (abstract), The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 24(4):324.
- 1962. "‘Flexible’ Predicates of Formal Number Theory," Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 13(4):647-650.
- 1962. "The Undecidability of Monadic Modal Quantification Theory", Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 8:113–116
- 1963. "Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic", Acta Philosophica Fennica 16:83–94
- 1963. "Semantical Analysis of Modal Logic I: Normal Modal Propositional Calculi", Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 9:67–96
- 1964. "Transfinite Recursions on Admissible Ordinals, I" (abstract), The Journal of Symbolic Logic, Vol. 29, No. 3, p. 162.
- 1964. "Transfinite Recursions on Admissible Ordinals, II" (abstract), The Journal of Symbolic Logic, Vol. 29, No. 3, p. 162.
- 1964. "Admissible Ordinals and the Analytic Hierarchy" (abstract), The Journal of Symbolic Logic, Vol. 29, No. 3, p. 162.
- 1965. "Semantical Analysis of Intuitionistic Logic I", In Formal Systems and Recursive Functions, edited by M. Dummett and J. N. Crossley. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Co.
- 1965. "Semantical Analysis of Modal Logic II: Non-Normal Modal Propositional Calculi", In The Theory of Models, edited by J. W. Addison, L. Henkin and A. Tarski. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Co.
- 1967. Research Announcement: "Deduction-preserving ‘Recursive Isomorphisms’ between Theories" (with Marian Boykan Pour-El), Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 73:145-148.
- 1967. "An Extension of a Theorem of Gaifman-Hales-Solovay," Fundamenta Mathematicae, Vol. 61, pp. 29–32.
- 1967. "Transfinite Recursion, Constructible Sets, and Analogues of Cardinals," Summaries of Talks Prepared in Connection with the Summer Institute on Axiomatic Set Theory, American Mathematical Society, U.C.L.A., pp. IV-0-1 - IV-0-12.
- 1967. "On the Application of Boolean-Valued Models to Solutions of Problems in Boolean Algebra," in Summaries of Talks Prepared in Connection with the Summer Institute on Axiomatic Set Theory, American Mathematical Society, U.C.L.A. (1967), pp. IV-T-1 through IV-T-7.
- 1967. "Deduction-preserving ‘Recursive Isomorphisms’ between Theories" (with Marian Boykan Pour-El), Fundamenta Mathematicae 61:141-163.
- 1971. "Identity and Necessity", In Identity and Individuation, edited by M. K. Munitz. New York: New York University Press.
- 1972 (1980). "Naming and Necessity", In Semantics of Natural Language, edited by D. Davidson and G. Harman. Dordrecht; Boston: Reidel. Sets out the causal theory of reference.
- 1975. "Outline of a Theory of Truth", Journal of Philosophy 72:690–716. Sets his theory of truth (against Alfred Tarski), where an object language can contain its own truth predicate.
- 1976. "Is There a Problem about Substitutional Quantification?", In Truth and Meaning: Essays in Semantics, edited by Gareth Evans and John McDowell. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- 1976. "A Theory of Truth I. Preliminary Report," abstract, Journal of Symbolic Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2, pp. 556.
- 1976. "A Theory of Truth II. Preliminary Report," abstract, Journal of Symbolic Logic, Vol. 41, No. 2, pp. 556–557.
- 1977. "Speaker's Reference and Semantic Reference", Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2:255–276.
- 1979. "A Puzzle about Belief", In Meaning and Use, edited by A. Margalit. Dordrecht and Boston: Reidel.
- 1982. "Nonstandard Models of Peano Arithmetic" (with S. Kochen), in Logic and Algorithmics: International Symposium Held in Honor of Ernst Specker, H. Lauchli (ed.), University of Geneva: 277-295.
- 1986. “A Problem in the Theory of Reference: the Linguistic Division of Labor and the Social Character of Naming,” Philosophy and Culture (Proceedings of the XVIIth World Congress of Philosophy), Montreal, Editions Montmorency: 241-247.
- 1992. “Summary: Individual Concepts: Their Logic, Philosophy, and Some of Their Uses.” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 66: 70-73
- 2005. "Russell's Notion of Scope", Mind 114:1005–1037
- 2008. "Frege’s Theory of Sense and Reference: Some Exegetical Notes,” Theoria 74:181-218
- 2009. "Presupposition and Anaphora: Remarks on the formulation of the projection problem," Linguistic Inquiry 40(3):367-386.
- 2009. "The Collapse of the Hilbert Program," (Abstract) Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 15(2):229-231.
- 2011. "The First Person," Collected Papers Vol. I, Oxford University Press. The videos "The First Person" and "Questions and Answers" in which the paper is based are available here.
- 2011. "Two Paradoxes of Knowledge," Collected Papers Vol. I, Oxford University Press.
- 2011. "Nozick on Knowledge," Collected Papers Vol. I, Oxford University Press.
- 2011. "A Puzzle about Time and Thought," Collected Papers Vol. I, Oxford University Press.
- 2011. "Vacuous Names and Fictional Entities," Collected Papers Vol. I, Oxford University Press.
- 2011. "Unrestricted Exportation and Some Morals for the Philosophy of Language," Collected Papers Vol. I, Oxford University Press. Podcast of the talk available here.
- (Forthcoming). “Another Approach: The Church-Turing ‘Thesis’ as a Special Corollary of Gödel’s Completeness Theorem,” in Computability: Gödel, Turing, Church, and beyond, Copeland, B. J., Posy, C., and Shagrir, O. (eds), Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press.
- 1963. “History and Idealism: the Theory of R. G. Collingwood”.
- 1973. John Locke Lectures: "Reference and Existence". (Transcript available in the Philosophy Library, Oxford University)
- 1975. "Three Lectures on Truth". Princeton University. Discussed here.
- 197-. “On The Completeness and Decidability of Intuitionistic Propositional Logic”.
- 1978. "Time and Identity". Seminar given at Princeton University, 1978. Several versions of this material have circulated. Some of its ideas are discussed by Ted Sider in his book Four-Dimensionalism: An Ontology of Persistence and Time
- 19- "Non-Standard Models and Godel's Theorem: A Model-Theoretic Proof of Godel's Theorem". Summary by Hilary Putnam.
- 1984. "Lessons on Functionalism and Automata". (Delivered at the International Wittgenstein Symposium, 1984. Transcribed by Roderick Chisholm.[14]
- 198-. “A Proof of Gamma.”
- 198-. “A Note on Zabludowski’s Critique of Goodman’s Theory of Projection”.
- 1986. “Rigid Designation and the Contingent A Priori: The Meter Stick Revisited” (Notre Dame, 1986).
- 1988/89. "Seminars on Truth". Three-semester seminar at Princeton in 1988-89, only the first two semesters have been transcribed by Jim Cain. See here.
- 19- "Semantical Analysis of Intuitionistic Logic II. Undecidability of the Monadic Fragment" (Undated manuscript).
- 19- "Semantical Analysis of Intuitionistic Logic III" (Undated manuscript).
- 1989. "No Fool's Red? Some Considerations on the Primary/Secondary Quality Distinction"(includes comments by David Velleman). University of Michigan, 1989.
- 1992. Whitehead Lectures: "Logicism, Wittgenstein, and De Re Beliefs about Natural Numbers". Delivered at Harvard University, 1992.
- 1992. "Individual Concepts: Their Logic, Philosophy, and Some of Their Uses". Transcribed by Stephen Webb.
- 1996.“The Ordered Pair: A Philosophical Paradigm Revisited”.
- 1996. "Elementary Recursion Theory and its Applications to Formal Systems." Transcribed by Mario Gomez Torrente and John Barker. Index available here.
- 1999. "The Road to Gödel". (Read at Haifa University, Israel, 1999. Several transcripts exist.
- 2006. "From Church's Thesis to the First Order Algorithm Theorem," Tel Aviv University, June 13, 2006. Video available here and abstract available here.
- 2007. "Roundtable on Externalism" (Hilary Putnam, Tyler Burge, Saul Kripke, and Michael Devitt). University College Dublin, Ireland. Podcast available here.
- 2007. "The Collapse of the Hilbert Program". Indiana University, Presidential Lecture. Video available here.
- 2008. “Mathematical Incompleteness Results in Peano Arithmetic, a Revisionist View of the Early History”.
- "New Frontiers in American Philosophy" by Taylor Branch, New York Times Magazine, August 14, 1977.
- "Saul Kripke, Genius Logician." Interview by Andreas Saugstad, February 25, 2001.
- "Celebrating CUNY's Genius Philosopher" by Gary Shapiro, The New York Sun, January 27, 2006.
- "Philosopher, 65, Lectures Not About 'What Am I?' but 'What Is I?'" by Charles McGrath, The New York Times, January 28, 2006.
- "The Best Five Books on the Philosophy of Language" by Scott Soames, October 15, 2010.
- ^ Brian Leiter, Leiter Reports: A Philosophy Blog, "So who *is* the most important philosopher of the past 200 years?"
- ^ Jerry Fodor, "Water's water everywhere", London Review of Books, 21 October 2004
- ^ Kripke, Saul (2011). Philosophical Troubles: Collected Papers Volume 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. xii. ISBN 978-0-19-973015-5.
- ^ Charles McGrath (2006-01-28). "Philosopher, 65, Lectures Not About 'What Am I?' but 'What Is I?'". The New York Times. http://www.nytimes.com/2006/01/28/books/28krip.html?pagewanted=1&ei=5088&en=9b8c06355a8dc486&ex=1296104400&adxnnl=0&partner=rssnyt&emc=rss&adxnnlx=1156068875-xI9kVaL9WqHJhRK5STWHrw. Retrieved 2008-01-23.
- ^ A Companion to Analytic Philosophy (Blackwell Companions to Philosophy), by A. P. Martinich (Editor), E. David Sosa (Editor), 38. Saul Kripke (1940–)
- ^ Fludernik, Monika. "Histories of Narrative Theory: From Structuralism to Present." A Companion to Narrative Theory. Ed. Phelan and Rabinowitz. Blackwell Publishing, MA:2005.
- ^ Chalmers, David. 1996. The Conscious Mind. Oxford University Press pp. 146-9.
- ^ Smith, Quentin (2 August 2001). "Marcus, Kripke, and the Origin of the New Theory of Reference". Synthese 104 (2): 179–189. DOI:10.1007/BF01063869. http://www.qsmithwmu.com/marcus,_kripke,_and_the_origin_of_the_new_theory_of_reference.htm. Retrieved 2007-05-28.
- ^ Stephen Neale (9 February 2001). "No Plagiarism Here" (.PDF). Times Literary Supplement 104 (2): 12–13. DOI:10.1007/BF01063869. http://web.gc.cuny.edu/philosophy/people/neale/papers/NealeKripke.pdf. Retrieved 2009-11-13. [dead link]
- ^ Kripke, 1980, p. 20
- ^ Stern, David G. 2006. Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press. p. 2
- ^ "Kripke is Jewish, and he takes this seriously. He is not a nominal Jew and he is careful keeping the Sabbath, for instance he doesn't use public transportation on Saturdays." Andreas Saugstad, "Saul Kripke: Genius logician", 25 February 2001.
- ^ Andreas Saugstad, "Saul Kripke: Genius logician", 25 February 2001.
- ^ Edward P. Stabler, ""Kripke on functionalism and automata", Synthese, Vol. 70 No. 1 (1987).
- Taylor Branch (1977), "New Frontiers in American Philosophy: Saul Kripke". New York Times Magazine.
- Nathan Salmon (1981), Reference and Essence. ISBN 1-59102-215-0 ISBN 978-1591022152.
- Consuelo Preti (2002), On Kripke. Wadsworth. ISBN 0-534-58366-0.
- Scott Soames (2002), Beyond Rigidity: The Unfinished Semantic Agenda of Naming and Necessity. ISBN 0-19-514529-1.
- Christopher Hughes (2004), Kripke : Names, Necessity, and Identity. ISBN 0-19-824107-0.
- G.W. Fitch (2005), Saul Kripke. ISBN 0-7735-2885-7.
- Martin Kusch (2006), A sceptical Guide to Meaning and Rules. Defending Kripke's Wittgenstein. Acumben: Publishing Limited.
- Arif Ahmed (2007), Saul Kripke. New York, NY; London: Continuum. ISBN 0-8264-9262-2.
- Christopher Norris (2007), Fiction, Philosophy and Literary Theory: Will the Real Saul Kripke Please Stand Up? London: Continuum
- CUNY Graduate Center Philosophy Department faculty page
- The Saul Kripke Center, at the CUNY Graduate Center
- Saul Kripke at the Mathematics Genealogy Project
- Saul Kripke, Genius Logician A short, non-technical interview by Andreas Saugstad, February 25, 2001.
- The conference in honor of Kripke's sixty-fifth birthday with a video of his speech "The First Person", January 25–26, 2006
- Video of his talk "From Church's Thesis to the First Order Algorithm Theorem," June 13, 2006.
- Podcast of his talk "Unrestricted Exportation and Some Morals for the Philosophy of Language," May 21, 2008.
- London Review of Books article by Jerry Fodor discussing Kripke's work
- Celebrating CUNY's Genius Philosopher, by Gary Shapiro, January 27, 2006, in The New York Sun.
- information from 'Philosophy Professor' website
- A New York Times article about his 65th birthday
- Roundtable on Kripke's critique of mind-body identity with Scott Soames as the main presenter May 26, 2010.
|
|
Overview
|
|
Academic
areas |
|
|
Foundational
concepts |
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
|
Logic and philosophy |
|
|
Mathematics |
|
|
Musical arts |
|
|
Visual arts |
|
|
Persondata |
Name |
Kripke, Aaron |
Alternative names |
|
Short description |
|
Date of birth |
November 13, 1940 |
Place of birth |
Bay Shore, New York |
Date of death |
|
Place of death |
|